In every world, Crusius notes, things interact by moving, thus movement is a topic that should be studied in cosmology. More precisely, he continues, the topic of movement can be approached with three questions: what is movement, how it can be measured and what laws govern it. Of these three, Crusius explains, the first one is clearly cosmological, while the second one was dealt in ontology. The third one, Crusius concludes, is partially cosmological, because some laws of movement can be deduced from the very essence of movement, although some laws of movement must be proven empirically and thus belong to physics.
Crusius then defines movement as a state of a substance that changes its place. Its opposite is rest or a state where a thing does not change its place. Crusius notes also that some movement is only apparent, when a thing does not change its absolute place, but only its place in relation to some other thing. True change, where a thing changes its absolute place, he further divides into external change, where the whole thing is moving, and internal change, where some actual parts of a thing change their places so that their positions in relation to other parts of the whole are changed. Crusius points out that these two classes are not mutually exclusive, since there can occur situations where a thing moves, while its parts change their place in relation to one another.
What then could move in these different ways? Crusius notes that a simple substance cannot at least move internally, since it doesn’t have any actual parts. Then again, infinite things (or from Crusius’ perspective, God) cannot move externally, because there is nowhere where such an infinite thing could move as a whole. Furthermore, he adds, everything that is finite, can move at least externally, whether it is simple or complex.
Crusius divides external movement into total external movement, where the whole substance moves completely from one location to another, and partial external movement, where actual or ideal parts of the thing change their place: once again, the two classes are not mutually exclusive. While the notion of total external movement seems clear enough, it might be difficult to see how partial external movement differs from internal movement. One example of a partial external movement that is not internal nor total, Crusius says, is such where a simple substance grows and thus its ideal parts change their places, since this involves no change of actual, distinct parts of the substance. Another example would be rotation of a sphere: the sphere as a whole does not go from one location to another and the relative positions of its parts remain the same, but the parts of the sphere do change their absolute positions.
Crusius derives some simple consequences from his definition of movement. Movement, as he sees it, has always a definite direction, and indeed, a start and end point. It also has certain characteristics: velocity and strength by which it withstands resistance. Furthermore, Crusius notes that movement of a complex substance is defined by the movement of its parts.
Movement, Crusius emphasises, is a positive change and thus requires a positive cause. Rest, on the other hand, is for Crusius just a lack of movement and does not therefore require any cause. In other words, a thing rests, Crusius says, if it has no reason to move, and if the cause of the movement vanishes, the movement must also cease. A direct consequence of this is that increase in the velocity of movement requires a similar increase in the cause of the movement. Crusius also thinks that change of the direction of the movement must also have a cause, which would make the Epicurean idea of atoms swerving without a reason ridiculous.
Because motion always requires some cause, Crusius continues, state of movement cannot be indifferent to the matter. By this Crusius means that a moving cause has to at first overcome an inherent resistance in moving a piece of matter. This inherent resistance is, of course, inertia. More precisely, Crusius calls it metaphysical inertia, distinguishing it from physical inertia, where the resistance is not just an inherent property of matter, but also involves a force, although one that is, as it were, dead, that is, suppressed by the moving force. Beyond inertia, motion can be resisted also by a living force, that is, a force that truly can resist the moving cause.
Crusius notes that a finite cause of movement cannot really affect a thing more than the thing resists the movement. Of course, the cause can have more force, but it only uses as much force as is required for overcoming the resistance. Thus, Crusius thinks he has justified the law of action being equal to reaction. Although a non-empirical proof, Crusius clarifies, we still require empirical observations to determine how much a finite cause acts at a given situation.
It is an essential feature of substances that differ from God, Crusius says, that they cannot penetrate one another. Thus, when a finite substance, whether matter or spirit, tries to occupy the same place as another finite substance, it will drive away the other substance, that is, pushes it. Crusius adds that pushing is just an existential effect, in other words, it doesn’t require any force, but the mere presence of one substance trying to occupy the place of the other.
Pushing a substance makes it move: Crusius calls this a communicated movement. Indeed, he says, communicating movement is the only way finite substances can affect one another. Series of communicated movements cannot go on forever, he immediately adds, and such series cannot all derive from God’s miracles, because that would be against the purpose of the world. Thus, Crusius argues, there must be some finite substances that can move their own substance through their inner activity - such movement he calls original. The inner activity causing original movement can be constant or conditional striving, inherent to some elements of material things, or it can be free willing. Because even the activity of elements is ultimately derived from God, Crusius concludes, all movement is generated by some spiritual activity that is not movement.
Communicated movement, Crusius notes, need not always be just an effect of the impenetrability of finite substances, but can also involve an inner activity of a substance. He is thus against the Cartesian idea that interactions of material things would have to be explained solely through geometric properties: God can give material things some inner activities. Crusius faces the possible objection that such activities are what were disparagingly called occult qualities by noting that we can know such activities as well as finite creatures can, when we can distinguish them from one another and deduce their existence from their effects.
Crusius progresses then to describe several rules involved in the communication of movement, such as parallelogram rule and behaviour of elastic substances. I will not follow him to these details, but I shall take a look at a few conundrums concerning movement that Crusius considers. First of these involves the question of the quantity of movement in the world: is it always constant? Crusius’ answer clearly has to be negative, because this would preclude the possibility of spirits to interact with the world. He even denies the weaker assumption that the world would have a constant amount of moving force, because spirits should be able to choose how strongly they move other things.
Another conundrum concerns the question whether all the matter in the world is moving constantly. A reason for upholding such an opinion would be that a constant movement is required for explaining why shapes of things remain stable: without the constant movement of the surrounding matter, a thing could just change willy-nilly its shape. Crusius does not find this argument convincing. The shape of a complex thing is determined by the shape and position of its parts, while the shape of a simple thing is either chosen by God, with or without any reason, or caused by themselves or by external forces - where is the need for movement here?
The answer to the question, Crusius concludes, belongs to physical, not metaphysical cosmology. He does state that the ultimate limits of the world cannot move and similarly all things that God has determined to rest. Other things, then, probably at least strive to move, whether through their own inherent activity or through being spurred to movement by things outside them.
Finally, Crusius ponders the question whether movement of one material thing necessarily sets all other material things in motion. He notes that if the world contains spaces void of any finite things, movement of one thing could go through this void without communicating movement to other things. Furthermore, he continues, even if there is no void, certain material things could also just switch places without affecting other material things.
Crusius also thinks that these arguments disprove the idea endorsed often by Wolffians that from state of any substance in the world could be determined the state of all other substances. This proposition of Wolffians was explicitly based on the supposed continuous causal nexus of all the parts of the world, where movement of one piece would eventually affect all the other pieces. If this nexus fails, as Crusius deems very possible, the states of the substances in the world would not be as closely interlinked, although they would be really connected.
Näytetään tekstit, joissa on tunniste cosmology. Näytä kaikki tekstit
Näytetään tekstit, joissa on tunniste cosmology. Näytä kaikki tekstit
perjantai 3. helmikuuta 2023
torstai 26. tammikuuta 2023
Christian August Crusius: Draft of necessary truths of reason, in so far as they are set opposite to contingent ones - The essence of the world
After going through what can be known about God, Crusius continues with the question of the world. His aim is to do metaphysical cosmology, that is, to describe what any world in general must be like and what we can know about this necessary essence of worlds without any help of prior experience. Thus, metaphysical cosmology in Crusius’ sense is not a physical endeavour and does not aim to describe our actual world.
Crusius faces the problem that since we do not even know our actual world completely and certainly don’t know what all the possible worlds are like, it seems impossible for us to know what worlds would necessarily be like. He admits that metaphysical cosmology must be incomplete. Firstly, he says, only God could know all the possible characteristics a world could have. Secondly, we are unsure even of many features of the actual world whether they are necessary: for instance, should every possible world have colours?
Despite these misgivings, Crusius thinks that we can still know some important truths of metaphysical cosmology. Firstly, all possible worlds are also things and thus must have characteristics that ontology has shown all things to have. Secondly, natural theology also implies things in cosmology, because any world would be God’s creation and would thus reflect their essential properties. Finally, he concludes, the very concept of the world must imply what a world must be like.
Furthermore, Crusius notes that we do not need to observe different possible worlds in order to form a distinct concept of a world - we just have to be able to distinguish a world from anything that is not a world. Firstly, Crusius distinguishes the world from God: the latter is necessary, the former is not. Secondly, a world is not an individual creature, but a sum of creatures, although, Crusius admits, God could have created just a single creature.
Not all collections of creatures are worlds, Crusius emphasises. Some collections are just connected by the observer, but a world should truly be a unity, not just in someone’s thoughts. Finally, Crusius notes, a world should be a real whole, not a part of something larger. Crusius’ final concept of the world is then that world is a real combination of finite things that is not again a part of another, to which it would belong through a real combination.
As a combination of things, Crusius says, every possible world must be spatial. In addition, because a world is particularly a combination of finite things, it must necessarily be of finite size. Crusius is especially keen to point out that although mathematics speaks of infinite spaces, this is just an abstract fiction that is not truly possible in a world. God, on the other hand, should exist wherever the world is, but God is not limited by the limits of the world. Crusius also accepts the possibility of world having void spaces in it - that is, spaces void of finite creatures, because God would exist even within void.
In addition to being spatial, Crusius continues, a world must also be temporal. He adds that because a world is created by God, it must have not existed at some point in time. World also could not exist by itself, even after creation, but must be sustained by God. Crusius appears to assume that God does not create anything else in the world after the first creation, but he does admit the possibility that some part of the world might have been isolated from another part for a while, while the two parts would later come in contact with one another. Thus, he suggests, the physical law of the constant quantity of forces is not as such necessary, because we cannot be sure that the world does not contain such isolated, unknown forces.
Crusius also emphasises that God has created the world for some purpose. As he has pointed out earlier, the purpose of creation has to serve especially the free creatures with the ability to reason. Thus, other things in the world must be either means for that purpose or then necessary consequences of creating and arranging the world to serve the purpose. Whatever the purpose of a particular possible world is, the world must be good, because its creator is also. Then again, no world can really be the best possible world, because all worlds are somehow imperfect and could be improved.
An interesting question Crusius considers is what belongs to an identity of a world: how much a world can be changed before it becomes a different world? Obviously, one could take the primary constituents of a world - simple substances - and reorder them in a different manner. Yet, this answer concerns only the ultimate metaphysical subject of what makes a world and ignores the intriguing problem of whether a world has some inherent structure that differentiates it from any other world made out of the same substances.
Crusius outlines next his criterion of a world’s identity: a world remains same, as long as it still serves its fundamental purpose and in particular no individual things, their combinations, laws governing them and their essential actions change in a manner that would change this inherent purpose or any means required for the fulfilment of that purpose. Any change that does not do this, he continues, merely changes the state of this world. Indeed, he points out an important type of change that does not change the identity of a world. A world is created for the sake of free creatures and for enabling their free actions. Thus, he suggests, whatever persons do freely should not affect the essence of the world they inhabit, because that would mean the very purpose of a world could contradict itself.
Because things in the world are combined, Crusius insists, they must be able to interact with one another. In these interactions some things must be active or affect one another, but Crusius notes that there can be passive things that do not have any force to affect other things, but at most enable something through their existence. Both active forces and inactive abilities can combine things into more complex wholes.
Furthermore, Crusius continues, interactions that combine things are governed by physical laws that should hold independently of our thinking of them. Crusius notes that there are also laws of understanding that merely say what propositions follow or are possible in certain circumstances, but these differ from real physical laws. Similarly, he distinguishes physical laws from moral laws, which say what should be done according to commands of some lord.
Now Crucius defines nature as the sum of all substances in the world, together with the physical laws governing their combinations. Natural is then something that happens through the fundamental forces of created substances, while God does nothing else, but sustains these substances and fundamental forces. Supernatural, on the other hand, is something caused immediately by God. Because at least the sustainment of the substances and their fundamental forces is an immediate effect of God’s action, Crusius concludes that every world has something supernatural in it.
Crusius thinks that we can conceive no other interaction between finite things than interaction through movement. Since we are dealing with finities, he continues, we can invoke the principle that this non-conceivability reveals a true dependence relation: finite things can affect one another only through movement. Thus, when a finite substance affects another, it either forces the other to move by its own impenetrability or then its motion awakens some other activity in the other substance.
This other activity that can be awakened by motion, Crusius insists, is either thinking or willing, which we know are not movement. He then distinguishes two kinds of substances in the world: material substances, which can only move, and spiritual substances, which move, but also think and will things. Furthermore, he divides matter into two further subclasses: metaphysical or inactive matter that has only a passive capacity for movement and physical or active matter that has also some active force.
Crusius has noted that the world has been made for the sake of free spirits, thus, the world must, undoubtedly, have spirits in it. One important consequence of the existence of free spirits is that Crusius’ world cannot be completely deterministic. A world need not have matter, on the other hand, but matter can exist in it. Then again, Crusius notes, because everything in the world must somehow serve its purpose or free spirits, matter and spirits must be able to interact: why else would God have created it? Crucius brushes aside the old Cartesian worry that spirit could not affect matter, because they are two different types of substances: dogs and humans share characteristics and still are of different species. Crusius sees no problem in accepting that spirits are also impenetrable, like matter, and can thus move and be moved by material objects.
Crusius is unsure about the Leibnizian principle that there are no two things that cannot be distinguished from one another. He does admit that no two spirits can be completely similar, because everyone of them perceives the world from a somewhat different perspective and perceptions change their inner state. The case is different with material substances, Crusius says. The principle itself cannot be justified without experience, he insists and thinks that all supposed proofs of the principle have been sophisms: if God would have wanted, two different and still completely similar material substances could have been created. True, he admits, experience appears to show that seemingly similar things often differ in some manner. Yet, there is no assurance that at least some of the simplest parts of matter wouldn’t be completely similar. Still, Crusius suggests, God has probably created at least many different kinds of simple material substances, because this would provide more means for helping the world to fulfil its purpose.
Whatever the ultimate elements of matter are like, they can be combined into more complex substances or bodies. Indeed, Crusius says, matter as a whole probably has to be dispersed into distinct bodies, because this better helps to achieve the purpose of the world. Crusius distinguishes physical from mathematical bodies, which are mere possible divisions of space. Physical bodies, instead, are not united just because we think of them as united, but through something real that separates them from other bodies. Crusius suggests three kinds of such unifications. Firstly, parts of a body can be held together by inactive, unmoving substances surrounding it. Secondly, parts of a body can be held together by moving substances surrounding it, such as the vortexes in Cartesian physics. Finally, parts of a body can be held together by an elastic matter, that is, matter that has an innate tendency to return to a certain shape.
No other ways to unite material things into bodies exist, Crusius insists. He is especially keen to deny any attractive or cohesive forces that would hold parts of a body together, because all explanations why material things stay together should be reducible to fundamental forces. Cohesive force cannot be a fundamental force, he adds, because cohesion is just another name for material parts staying together and so merely describes the phenomenon without explaining it. Then again, Crusius denies the existence of attractive force, because such an action in distance breaks the requirements of what a force and causal interaction should be like. Finally, Crusius also denies that parts of bodies would stay together because of common feeling, since feeling is something he allows only spirits to have.
However the bodies are held together, they then interact with one another and with the spirits. Despite the interaction between the two types of substances, Crusius notes, these different classes can also be regarded in abstraction from one another. Thus, spirits of the world, in separation from material things, form a spiritual world, while matter as such forms a material world, and when regarded as separated into distinct bodies, a bodily world.
The bodily world particularly, Crusius says, can be seen as a machine - that is, as a body of its own, combined from parts that are shaped for some purposes in such a manner that these purposes can be actualised with the aid of the shape and the position of these parts. This is not true, he adds, of the whole world, because this also includes spirits that cannot be parts of a body. Furthermore, he notes, although the bodily world is a machine, all its parts are not, for instance, a stone is just a body, but not a machine. Finally, Crusius points out that the bodily world is a rather peculiar machine, because part of its driving force comes from actions of free spirits.
Although spirits are not machines, they can be combined with naturally produced machines. Crusius is obviously speaking of organic bodies, combined to which spirits are called souls. Crusius suggests that it is not completely necessary that worlds contain animals or combinations of souls and organic bodies. Animals do make a world more perfect, but finite spirits should be able to affect the bodily world even without the help of a body of their own.
For Crusius, the world is not a deterministic whole, because it also contains spirits capable of free actions. God’s interactions with the world provide further reasons why determinism does not work. We’ve already seen Crusius to note that God has a constant supernatural effect on the world, for instance, in sustaining the world and all the substances in it. In addition to such constant effects, Crusius also thinks that God can occasionally have quite sudden effects on the world, that is, God might do miracles.
Some of the miracles can be hidden from us humans - they are done merely, because God thought it best to do things in such a manner. At other times, God might choose to reveal that a miracle has been done - in these cases, Crusius adds, God must want humans to know that some event was a miracle. Sometimes the miracle might appear to be a work of a person following God, but even in these cases it is God who actually gives the person a power for doing such miracles. In these cases, Crusius explains, it is futile to try to make experiments whether this person truly can consistently make miracles, because God can at any point just choose not to grant that power to the person anymore.
How then to know when some event has been a miracle? Crusius points out that because of the possibility of hidden miracles, we can never be sure that something hasn’t been a miracle. Yet, he also gives a general criteria for recognising miracles: something is a miracle, if it could not have happened in a natural manner generally or at least in these specific conditions. He also adds that we are sometimes very able to distinguish supernatural from natural events, because we are so familiar with what naturally happens: for instance, we know trees don’t usually talk. Crusius also points out that we do not need mathematically certain proofs to accept something as a miracle, but a lower grade of conviction is usually enough. Finally, he emphasises that miracles also have a moral aspect, that is, we shouldn’t think of something with immoral consequences as a miracle.
Crusius faces the problem that since we do not even know our actual world completely and certainly don’t know what all the possible worlds are like, it seems impossible for us to know what worlds would necessarily be like. He admits that metaphysical cosmology must be incomplete. Firstly, he says, only God could know all the possible characteristics a world could have. Secondly, we are unsure even of many features of the actual world whether they are necessary: for instance, should every possible world have colours?
Despite these misgivings, Crusius thinks that we can still know some important truths of metaphysical cosmology. Firstly, all possible worlds are also things and thus must have characteristics that ontology has shown all things to have. Secondly, natural theology also implies things in cosmology, because any world would be God’s creation and would thus reflect their essential properties. Finally, he concludes, the very concept of the world must imply what a world must be like.
Furthermore, Crusius notes that we do not need to observe different possible worlds in order to form a distinct concept of a world - we just have to be able to distinguish a world from anything that is not a world. Firstly, Crusius distinguishes the world from God: the latter is necessary, the former is not. Secondly, a world is not an individual creature, but a sum of creatures, although, Crusius admits, God could have created just a single creature.
Not all collections of creatures are worlds, Crusius emphasises. Some collections are just connected by the observer, but a world should truly be a unity, not just in someone’s thoughts. Finally, Crusius notes, a world should be a real whole, not a part of something larger. Crusius’ final concept of the world is then that world is a real combination of finite things that is not again a part of another, to which it would belong through a real combination.
As a combination of things, Crusius says, every possible world must be spatial. In addition, because a world is particularly a combination of finite things, it must necessarily be of finite size. Crusius is especially keen to point out that although mathematics speaks of infinite spaces, this is just an abstract fiction that is not truly possible in a world. God, on the other hand, should exist wherever the world is, but God is not limited by the limits of the world. Crusius also accepts the possibility of world having void spaces in it - that is, spaces void of finite creatures, because God would exist even within void.
In addition to being spatial, Crusius continues, a world must also be temporal. He adds that because a world is created by God, it must have not existed at some point in time. World also could not exist by itself, even after creation, but must be sustained by God. Crusius appears to assume that God does not create anything else in the world after the first creation, but he does admit the possibility that some part of the world might have been isolated from another part for a while, while the two parts would later come in contact with one another. Thus, he suggests, the physical law of the constant quantity of forces is not as such necessary, because we cannot be sure that the world does not contain such isolated, unknown forces.
Crusius also emphasises that God has created the world for some purpose. As he has pointed out earlier, the purpose of creation has to serve especially the free creatures with the ability to reason. Thus, other things in the world must be either means for that purpose or then necessary consequences of creating and arranging the world to serve the purpose. Whatever the purpose of a particular possible world is, the world must be good, because its creator is also. Then again, no world can really be the best possible world, because all worlds are somehow imperfect and could be improved.
An interesting question Crusius considers is what belongs to an identity of a world: how much a world can be changed before it becomes a different world? Obviously, one could take the primary constituents of a world - simple substances - and reorder them in a different manner. Yet, this answer concerns only the ultimate metaphysical subject of what makes a world and ignores the intriguing problem of whether a world has some inherent structure that differentiates it from any other world made out of the same substances.
Crusius outlines next his criterion of a world’s identity: a world remains same, as long as it still serves its fundamental purpose and in particular no individual things, their combinations, laws governing them and their essential actions change in a manner that would change this inherent purpose or any means required for the fulfilment of that purpose. Any change that does not do this, he continues, merely changes the state of this world. Indeed, he points out an important type of change that does not change the identity of a world. A world is created for the sake of free creatures and for enabling their free actions. Thus, he suggests, whatever persons do freely should not affect the essence of the world they inhabit, because that would mean the very purpose of a world could contradict itself.
Because things in the world are combined, Crusius insists, they must be able to interact with one another. In these interactions some things must be active or affect one another, but Crusius notes that there can be passive things that do not have any force to affect other things, but at most enable something through their existence. Both active forces and inactive abilities can combine things into more complex wholes.
Furthermore, Crusius continues, interactions that combine things are governed by physical laws that should hold independently of our thinking of them. Crusius notes that there are also laws of understanding that merely say what propositions follow or are possible in certain circumstances, but these differ from real physical laws. Similarly, he distinguishes physical laws from moral laws, which say what should be done according to commands of some lord.
Now Crucius defines nature as the sum of all substances in the world, together with the physical laws governing their combinations. Natural is then something that happens through the fundamental forces of created substances, while God does nothing else, but sustains these substances and fundamental forces. Supernatural, on the other hand, is something caused immediately by God. Because at least the sustainment of the substances and their fundamental forces is an immediate effect of God’s action, Crusius concludes that every world has something supernatural in it.
Crusius thinks that we can conceive no other interaction between finite things than interaction through movement. Since we are dealing with finities, he continues, we can invoke the principle that this non-conceivability reveals a true dependence relation: finite things can affect one another only through movement. Thus, when a finite substance affects another, it either forces the other to move by its own impenetrability or then its motion awakens some other activity in the other substance.
This other activity that can be awakened by motion, Crusius insists, is either thinking or willing, which we know are not movement. He then distinguishes two kinds of substances in the world: material substances, which can only move, and spiritual substances, which move, but also think and will things. Furthermore, he divides matter into two further subclasses: metaphysical or inactive matter that has only a passive capacity for movement and physical or active matter that has also some active force.
Crusius has noted that the world has been made for the sake of free spirits, thus, the world must, undoubtedly, have spirits in it. One important consequence of the existence of free spirits is that Crusius’ world cannot be completely deterministic. A world need not have matter, on the other hand, but matter can exist in it. Then again, Crusius notes, because everything in the world must somehow serve its purpose or free spirits, matter and spirits must be able to interact: why else would God have created it? Crucius brushes aside the old Cartesian worry that spirit could not affect matter, because they are two different types of substances: dogs and humans share characteristics and still are of different species. Crusius sees no problem in accepting that spirits are also impenetrable, like matter, and can thus move and be moved by material objects.
Crusius is unsure about the Leibnizian principle that there are no two things that cannot be distinguished from one another. He does admit that no two spirits can be completely similar, because everyone of them perceives the world from a somewhat different perspective and perceptions change their inner state. The case is different with material substances, Crusius says. The principle itself cannot be justified without experience, he insists and thinks that all supposed proofs of the principle have been sophisms: if God would have wanted, two different and still completely similar material substances could have been created. True, he admits, experience appears to show that seemingly similar things often differ in some manner. Yet, there is no assurance that at least some of the simplest parts of matter wouldn’t be completely similar. Still, Crusius suggests, God has probably created at least many different kinds of simple material substances, because this would provide more means for helping the world to fulfil its purpose.
Whatever the ultimate elements of matter are like, they can be combined into more complex substances or bodies. Indeed, Crusius says, matter as a whole probably has to be dispersed into distinct bodies, because this better helps to achieve the purpose of the world. Crusius distinguishes physical from mathematical bodies, which are mere possible divisions of space. Physical bodies, instead, are not united just because we think of them as united, but through something real that separates them from other bodies. Crusius suggests three kinds of such unifications. Firstly, parts of a body can be held together by inactive, unmoving substances surrounding it. Secondly, parts of a body can be held together by moving substances surrounding it, such as the vortexes in Cartesian physics. Finally, parts of a body can be held together by an elastic matter, that is, matter that has an innate tendency to return to a certain shape.
No other ways to unite material things into bodies exist, Crusius insists. He is especially keen to deny any attractive or cohesive forces that would hold parts of a body together, because all explanations why material things stay together should be reducible to fundamental forces. Cohesive force cannot be a fundamental force, he adds, because cohesion is just another name for material parts staying together and so merely describes the phenomenon without explaining it. Then again, Crusius denies the existence of attractive force, because such an action in distance breaks the requirements of what a force and causal interaction should be like. Finally, Crusius also denies that parts of bodies would stay together because of common feeling, since feeling is something he allows only spirits to have.
However the bodies are held together, they then interact with one another and with the spirits. Despite the interaction between the two types of substances, Crusius notes, these different classes can also be regarded in abstraction from one another. Thus, spirits of the world, in separation from material things, form a spiritual world, while matter as such forms a material world, and when regarded as separated into distinct bodies, a bodily world.
The bodily world particularly, Crusius says, can be seen as a machine - that is, as a body of its own, combined from parts that are shaped for some purposes in such a manner that these purposes can be actualised with the aid of the shape and the position of these parts. This is not true, he adds, of the whole world, because this also includes spirits that cannot be parts of a body. Furthermore, he notes, although the bodily world is a machine, all its parts are not, for instance, a stone is just a body, but not a machine. Finally, Crusius points out that the bodily world is a rather peculiar machine, because part of its driving force comes from actions of free spirits.
Although spirits are not machines, they can be combined with naturally produced machines. Crusius is obviously speaking of organic bodies, combined to which spirits are called souls. Crusius suggests that it is not completely necessary that worlds contain animals or combinations of souls and organic bodies. Animals do make a world more perfect, but finite spirits should be able to affect the bodily world even without the help of a body of their own.
For Crusius, the world is not a deterministic whole, because it also contains spirits capable of free actions. God’s interactions with the world provide further reasons why determinism does not work. We’ve already seen Crusius to note that God has a constant supernatural effect on the world, for instance, in sustaining the world and all the substances in it. In addition to such constant effects, Crusius also thinks that God can occasionally have quite sudden effects on the world, that is, God might do miracles.
Some of the miracles can be hidden from us humans - they are done merely, because God thought it best to do things in such a manner. At other times, God might choose to reveal that a miracle has been done - in these cases, Crusius adds, God must want humans to know that some event was a miracle. Sometimes the miracle might appear to be a work of a person following God, but even in these cases it is God who actually gives the person a power for doing such miracles. In these cases, Crusius explains, it is futile to try to make experiments whether this person truly can consistently make miracles, because God can at any point just choose not to grant that power to the person anymore.
How then to know when some event has been a miracle? Crusius points out that because of the possibility of hidden miracles, we can never be sure that something hasn’t been a miracle. Yet, he also gives a general criteria for recognising miracles: something is a miracle, if it could not have happened in a natural manner generally or at least in these specific conditions. He also adds that we are sometimes very able to distinguish supernatural from natural events, because we are so familiar with what naturally happens: for instance, we know trees don’t usually talk. Crusius also points out that we do not need mathematically certain proofs to accept something as a miracle, but a lower grade of conviction is usually enough. Finally, he emphasises that miracles also have a moral aspect, that is, we shouldn’t think of something with immoral consequences as a miracle.
keskiviikko 29. elokuuta 2018
Joachim Darjes: Elements of metaphysics 2 – The city of God
While the metaphysical compendiums in Wolffian tradition have usually ended with a look on natural theology, Darjes has left cosmology as the final chapter of his metaphysics. This makes some sort of sense, since he has already emphasised that cosmology is no proper part of metaphysics, since it does not deal with characteristics of all things or of things from one of the highest genera of things – cosmology is about world, which is a certain complex of things, consisting of many kinds of things (in Darjesian philosophy, material bodies and immaterial souls and spirits).
Another oddity is Darjes' inclusion of certain notions from natural law to his discussion. He is particularly interested of the concept of right and possession. Right to something, for Darjes, means that a person has the ability to use that something without hurting other persons or their rights. This seemingly innocuous definition allows Darjes to conclude that in fact God is the primary owner of everything – God surely can control everything that exists, and he cannot really hurt rights of others, since he made all things in the first place.
Darjesian definition has also important consequences for the rights of finite entities. Firstly, he notes that finite entities can really have rights only for complex things, because they have no power to do anything to simple entities. Secondly, since all things already belong to God originally, finite entities can have right to anything, only if God has provided them the right to use things in some manner.
In addition to owning everything, God also governs world. This means that he sets the goals toward which this ”city of God” strives. The main purpose divinity has set for everything, according to Darjes, is the happiness and perfection of all rational beings. Thus, Darjes concludes, all rational beings should strive for their own happiness and perfection and help others to find these also – and definitely not hinder others in their search.
Darjes does not go into particularities of what actions are good for happiness and perfection, but merely notes what tools God uses for guiding rational entities toward their appointed goal. Firstly, God can directly reveal some guidelines. Secondly, God might appoint further rewards and punishments and even a kind of heaven and hell, to provide further incitement for good actions. Despite these rather naive Christian notions, Darjes also supposes that all rational entities will eventually be able to perfect themselves – the purpose of punishments is also just to help personal perfection.
Another oddity is Darjes' inclusion of certain notions from natural law to his discussion. He is particularly interested of the concept of right and possession. Right to something, for Darjes, means that a person has the ability to use that something without hurting other persons or their rights. This seemingly innocuous definition allows Darjes to conclude that in fact God is the primary owner of everything – God surely can control everything that exists, and he cannot really hurt rights of others, since he made all things in the first place.
Darjesian definition has also important consequences for the rights of finite entities. Firstly, he notes that finite entities can really have rights only for complex things, because they have no power to do anything to simple entities. Secondly, since all things already belong to God originally, finite entities can have right to anything, only if God has provided them the right to use things in some manner.
In addition to owning everything, God also governs world. This means that he sets the goals toward which this ”city of God” strives. The main purpose divinity has set for everything, according to Darjes, is the happiness and perfection of all rational beings. Thus, Darjes concludes, all rational beings should strive for their own happiness and perfection and help others to find these also – and definitely not hinder others in their search.
Darjes does not go into particularities of what actions are good for happiness and perfection, but merely notes what tools God uses for guiding rational entities toward their appointed goal. Firstly, God can directly reveal some guidelines. Secondly, God might appoint further rewards and punishments and even a kind of heaven and hell, to provide further incitement for good actions. Despite these rather naive Christian notions, Darjes also supposes that all rational entities will eventually be able to perfect themselves – the purpose of punishments is also just to help personal perfection.
We are now finally finished with Darjesian metaphysics. Next up on the list is a return to the work of Martin Knutzen.
tiistai 12. tammikuuta 2016
Baumgarten: Metaphysics – Such a perfect world
The account of world
in general and its parts completes the independent part of
Baumgarten's cosmology. There is still one section of cosmology we
haven't dealt with, but it still requires to be fulfilled by an
important proposition, proven only in theology. The section concerns
the perfection of the world and the proposition to be proven states
that the world is perfect, because it is created by God.
We have already seen
that the notion of perfection in Baumgarten is quite aesthetical –
the more things we have following the same laws, the more perfect
world we have. This notion by itself rules out certain worldviews as
being clearly imperfect. We already know that Baumgarten holds materialistic world to be an impossibility. Furthermore, egoistic
world is clearly not perfect, because in such a world exists only one
entity. Similarly, a dualistic world is more perfect than idealistic,
because idealism allows only the existence of spirits, while dualism
accepts also the existence of matter and its simple parts – that
is, if matter and spirits are just something that can exist in the
same world.
One part of the
notion of perfection rules then that there should be as much entities
in the world as possible, while the other part states that these
entities should be governed by same laws. An interesting question is
whether the other part speaks against the possibility of events
happening against natural laws, that is, miracles. One thing is
certain – the inclusion of spirits in Baumgarten's world does not
violate natural laws, but instead just extends the notion of natural
from mere material universe to spiritual entities. Thus, whatever
spirits do, it is not in any way miraculous. Indeed, it is only God
who could act in any way against the laws of nature.
We might think that
as an avid Leibnizian Baumgarten would be quite against the notion of
miracles – in a perfect world God needs not wind the clock from
time to time. Yet, as a Wolffian, Baumgarten is still willing to
leave the possibility of miracles open. Supernatural events might be
possible even in the perfect world, if they just somehow improved the
world. If some perfections could not be achieved through mere natural
means or if they could not be achieved as perfectly, then miracles
might be in order.
Interestingly,
Baumgarten uses the notion of perfect world to decide the topical
question of interaction between substances. If we begin from the
least acceptable alternative, occasionalism would state that no
finite substances would actually act, but everything would be done by
infinite substance or God. This view would contradict a proposition
Baumgarten takes to be self-evident, that is, that when a thing is in
some respect passive toward another thing, it must be in another
respect active. Hence, occasionalism would fall to a contradiction
and would be unacceptable even on that account.
The decision between
causal influx, Leibnizian pre-established harmony and some mixture of
the two is not as simple. Before Baumgarten can decide between these
alternatives, he must obviously explain what they all mean. Causal
influx, Baumgarten says, means that all interactions are real, that
is, when substance A is active in respect to a change in passive
substance B, B is in no respect active in respect to this same
change. Then again, pre-established harmony states that all
interactions are ideal, that is, when substance A is active in
respect to a change in passive substance B, B is also active in
respect to that same change – in other words, it is just a matter
of perspective, whether A has caused something in B or whether B has
caused it in itself. In mixed positions, some interactions are real,
some ideal.
Now, Baumgarten
insists that the system of pre-established harmony does not deny that
causal interactions do occur between different substances – it just
states that at the same time these substances, in a sense, act for
themselves. Similarly, a system of universal causal influx does not
deny that world would contain universal harmony, and indeed, causal
influx would glue all the parts of the world as well together as
pre-established harmony. Then again, causal influx does have its
problems. Particularly, since an activity of a thing must always be
derived from some other substance, eventually no finite substance
would be active in the sense that its activity would be consequence
of its own nature.
But the final proof
Baumgarten accepts is based on the notion perfect world. If the world
would be glued by a universal causal influx, all the reasons for some
event would be external to the things involved in the event. Then
again, in pre-established harmony, all events have two different
types of influence – the events are really caused by the things
themselves and ideally by other things. Because of this
consideration, Baumgarten is willing to accept pre-established
harmony, except in case of God, who obviously is a real cause of the whole world.
So much for
cosmology! Next time I will turn to questions of psychology.
torstai 31. joulukuuta 2015
Baumgarten: Metaphysics – Elements of the world
Just like with
ontology, in cosmology Baumgarten appears to be rather close on
Wolff's ideas, but a more careful study reveals important
differences. One interesting point of distinction concerns the
question what belongs in a world. With Wolff, it appears that souls
do not exist within deterministic universe, but follow their own causal
series. With Baumgarten, on the other hand, souls appear to be just
as much part of the world as material objects. Thus, while for Wolff,
egoism is a statement on what there exists in general (nothing but
one soul), for Baumgarten it is a cosmological proposition (world
consists of one soul or is simple).
Reason for
Baumgarten's inclusion of souls in world might be his commitment to
Leibnizian notion of monads. True, even Wolff had said that monads do
correspond to what he called elements, but this admission was a bit
halfhearted. Baumgarten, instead, is quite insistent on using the
term monad. He even endorses the notion that these monads have some
soul-like properties, by stating that materialists must deny monads,
either in general or at least as parts of the world – because
Baumgarten, like Wolff, believes that all complex substances consist
of simple substances, which he identifies with monads, he can then
simply deny materialism as contradictory.
While it is
difficult to say what is the relation of elements and space in
Wolff's philosophy – and even more difficult to say what is the
relation of souls and space – Baumgarten states at once that monads
are located at some point in space. They are still not mere points in
space, because they also represent the world around them, some
darkly, others clearly (idealism is then defined as the idea that all
monads represent world clearly or are spirits).
Wolff was almost
silent on how his elements combined into, first corpuscles, then
visible material bodies – for instance, should we need an infinity
of them? Baumgarten does not provide a full explanation either, but
he at least has a more detailed story to tell. First of all, monads
are spatially located, that is, they must be in some sense positioned
in relation to one another. Now, this positionality was reduced in
Baumgarten's philosophy to interactions – being near another thing
meant just affecting it.
Now, Baumgarten held
that monads in some sense affect one another. In fact, when one monad
acts one another, this other monad must also react on the other
monad. Such interlocking combinations of monads form them more stable
connections. Their interaction forms their contact, and if no
external reason makes them lose their contact, the monads stay
together, forming a relatively stable material body.
Just like in
Wolffian philosophy, with Baumgarten the activities of monads explain
all phenomena on the level of bodies. Indeed, Baumgarten even says
that because all monads are active and e.g. change constantly their
relative positions (that is, start and cancel interactions with one
another), bodies also must be in constant movement.
Although Baumgarten
thus uses the language of monads interacting one another, it is still
unclear how seriously this statement is to be taken. Does Baumgarten,
like Wolff, admit interactions only with some primary elements, but
deny it between spiritual and other monads? Or does he accept or deny
all monadic interactions? These questions, along with the problematic
of a perfection of the world, will be dealt next time.
perjantai 25. joulukuuta 2015
Baumgarten: Metaphysics – World in general
A central part of
Wolffian cosmology was the notion of a possible world – an
alternative to the actual world. The notion appears also in
Baumgarten's cosmology, but the nature of these worlds is necessarily
quite different. In Wolff, it seems that these worlds are meant to be
individual entities, although not actual – they are thoughts flying
in God's mind, but infinitely detailed and thus completely
determinate. With Baumgarten, on the other hand, there are no
non-actual individuals, thus, merely possible worlds can be nothing
but universals.
Indeed, what we are
dealing with in Baumgarten's cosmology is more like a notion or
concept of world – Baumgarten starts from the actual world and
abstracts certain features that belong to the world. One could then
add more features to these features of ”world in general” and
these combinations might even be non-contradictory and therefore
possible – yet, these combinations would still have an extension of
at most one individual thing, that is, they would be predicates of
actual world or no world at all.
World, for
Baumgarten, is then such a series of actual finite entities, which is
not a part of any other series. Without further ado, Baumgarten
simply accepts that there is such a totality of actual finite
entities, although nothing speaks against the possibility that we
might have only a series of ever larger collections of finite
entities.
World is not just a
combination of finite entities, but an ordering of them, for
Baumgarten. Indeed, there are several nexuses holding worldly
entities together – causal chains and series of ends, for instance.
It is then an important part of the very concept of a world that is
must have some regularity and coherence – otherwise, it wouldn't
even be unified. By this statement, Baumgarten denies that fables or
faery tales could form any possible world.
Because world
consists of finities, it cannot be completely good, but must contain
some badness or imperfection. In particular, Baumgarten says, world
cannot be completely necessary. Thus, Baumgarten can deny Spinoza's
theory that world would be necessary. Then again, the existence of
the world works also against an acosmicist interpretation of Spinoza
– there is something else beyond God.
So much for the
general notion of world, next time we shall see what Baumgarten has
to say about the elements of the world.
lauantai 1. marraskuuta 2014
Gottsched: First grounds of whole worldly wisdom (1733)
I've already described Gottsched's original take on poetry and I am now about to embark on the first part of his work on the whole of philosophy, Erste Gründe der gesammten Weltweisheit, and especially its first part that deals with theoretical philosophy. Since, the number of such philosophical compendiums is about to grow and I assume they mostly follow the same formula, I am not about to make a thorough series of posts about each individual book on metaphysics. Instead, I shall merely make some general remarks and comment on the novel features of each work.
Before starting the work itself, Gottsched begins with a short presentation of the history of philosophy, and just like the pietist Joachim Lange, begins with the account of Genesis. Whereas Lange's vision of philosophy was one of depressing downhill, in which humans had lost the original wisdom that consisted of a connection to God, Gottsched has a more positive view, no doubt tied to a very different idea of what philosophy is all about: for Gottsched, just like for Wolff, philosophy is worldly wisdom, which then is a science for discovering happiness in this world, which can clearly become more perfect as we discover more things about the world around us. Curiously, Gottsched's take on history is rather unhistorical: he goes through nations and asks what philosophical or scientific discoveries they had made. This feeling of ahistoricity is heightened by Gottsched's decision to end the history of philosophy quickly after Socrates.
Before starting the work itself, Gottsched begins with a short presentation of the history of philosophy, and just like the pietist Joachim Lange, begins with the account of Genesis. Whereas Lange's vision of philosophy was one of depressing downhill, in which humans had lost the original wisdom that consisted of a connection to God, Gottsched has a more positive view, no doubt tied to a very different idea of what philosophy is all about: for Gottsched, just like for Wolff, philosophy is worldly wisdom, which then is a science for discovering happiness in this world, which can clearly become more perfect as we discover more things about the world around us. Curiously, Gottsched's take on history is rather unhistorical: he goes through nations and asks what philosophical or scientific discoveries they had made. This feeling of ahistoricity is heightened by Gottsched's decision to end the history of philosophy quickly after Socrates.
After this pseudohistorical introduction begins the work itself. Gottsched's take on what belongs to theoretical philosophy is pretty traditional: the book considers much the same topics as Wolff had done in his logical, metaphysical and physical writings. Still, Gottsched's arrangement of these topics is rather peculiar. After logic comes metaphysics, but this contains only ontology and cosmology. Metaphysics is followed by physics, which is then followed by a section on pneumatology, study of spirits. I shall briefly go through all novel and surprising features in Gottsched's treatment of these topics.
Gottsched's logic does not at first sight hold much surprises and seems rather Woffian in tone. True, Gottsched does mention other philosophers as inspirations of the study of logic, but it is clearly Wolffian logic, which Gottsched thinks is nearest to the truth: he explicitly mentions Wolff's German logic, while the organisation of the logic reveals clear influences of Latin logic. Still, Gottschedian logic has tendencies not existing in Wolff's logic. While Wolff accepted experience as one source of cognition among many others, Gottsched instead tries to reduce empirical judgements to reasoning. His justification is rather original: empirical judgements depend on the reliability of our sensory apparatus, but this is something that might be proved (for instance, Descartes tried to justify it by relying of the goodness of God). One could protest that such a reliability guarantees still only a probability of empirical judgements, but not necessarily their truth. Yet, this still would not be fatal to Gottsched's position, because in the Wolffian tradition probabilities were also something that could be reasoned with.
Although Gottsched mentions no names, it is clear even from the chapter divisions that he is closely following Wolff's Latin Ontology. The only clear deviation is the lack of a direct proof of the principle of sufficient reason. Instead, Gottsched favours the transcendental argument that this principle is required to distinguish dreams from reality. As this had been done by previous Wolffians, it still means no great leap forward. The other part of Gottschedian metaphysics, cosmology, seems at first sight also rather Wolffian. But while the details truly are lifted almost verbatim from Wolff's works, there is something novel in Gottsched's separation of cosmology as a part of metaphysics from the pneumatology that does not belong to metaphysics. Gottsched explains this division by noting that world must be a topic of metaphysics, because souls also are part of the world. Now, this is something that was at least unclear in Wolffian account of philosophy, and in fact, it is much easier to see Wolffian souls as not belonging to the world, which is causally closed whole, which souls most likely cannot directly interact with.
Gottsched's account of physics is, as is to be expected, full of references to sources beyond Wolff – Gottsched is drawing on developments that were still unknown in time of Wolff's physical writings. Most of what Gottsched recounts feels nowadays very trite – like the account of Ptolemaic and Copernican systems and Kepler's discoveries – or then quite dated – like a theory that first chapter of Genesis describes a time when Earth was still not rotating and each day took one year, while the dust covering Earth's surface slowly flew away, first to reveal light and only couple of ”days” or years later the Sun and the Moon.
What is truly revolutionary in Wolffian setting is Gottsched's pneumatology, which contains, in addition to empirical and rational psychology, also natural theology (God is also, after all, a spirit). We might firstly note that by the time Gottsched was writing this work, Wolff had not yet published Latin versions of these themes. What is truly novel is not Gottsched's new arrangement of topics, but Gottsched's rejection of the pre-established harmony as the explanation of soul/body – interaction.
This development seems remarkable at first, but in some sense is quite natural. We've seen that Wolff moved to a position, in which the pre-established harmony had only a status of a likely hypothesis. Gottsched now suggests that if it at this stage all theories are mere hypothesis and none of them is truly certain, we should choose the option that is most familiar – that is, the theory of a true interaction between soul and body. The problem how souls as substances beyond world can have any effect on world as a closed series of causes and effects Gottsched solves easily through his earlier admission that souls are part of the world and thus the soul/body -interaction belongs to the natural course of events.
Gottsched's pneumatology thus shows a new tendency in Wolffian school. Furthermore, Gottsched wasn't even the only figure to do this. He explicitly refers to a study of one Martin Knutsen - best known as the teacher of Kant - in which the interaction was defended. But what did Wolff himself had to say about the topic? We shall see soon, as I am now about to embark on Wolff's rational psychology.
Gottsched's logic does not at first sight hold much surprises and seems rather Woffian in tone. True, Gottsched does mention other philosophers as inspirations of the study of logic, but it is clearly Wolffian logic, which Gottsched thinks is nearest to the truth: he explicitly mentions Wolff's German logic, while the organisation of the logic reveals clear influences of Latin logic. Still, Gottschedian logic has tendencies not existing in Wolff's logic. While Wolff accepted experience as one source of cognition among many others, Gottsched instead tries to reduce empirical judgements to reasoning. His justification is rather original: empirical judgements depend on the reliability of our sensory apparatus, but this is something that might be proved (for instance, Descartes tried to justify it by relying of the goodness of God). One could protest that such a reliability guarantees still only a probability of empirical judgements, but not necessarily their truth. Yet, this still would not be fatal to Gottsched's position, because in the Wolffian tradition probabilities were also something that could be reasoned with.
Although Gottsched mentions no names, it is clear even from the chapter divisions that he is closely following Wolff's Latin Ontology. The only clear deviation is the lack of a direct proof of the principle of sufficient reason. Instead, Gottsched favours the transcendental argument that this principle is required to distinguish dreams from reality. As this had been done by previous Wolffians, it still means no great leap forward. The other part of Gottschedian metaphysics, cosmology, seems at first sight also rather Wolffian. But while the details truly are lifted almost verbatim from Wolff's works, there is something novel in Gottsched's separation of cosmology as a part of metaphysics from the pneumatology that does not belong to metaphysics. Gottsched explains this division by noting that world must be a topic of metaphysics, because souls also are part of the world. Now, this is something that was at least unclear in Wolffian account of philosophy, and in fact, it is much easier to see Wolffian souls as not belonging to the world, which is causally closed whole, which souls most likely cannot directly interact with.
Gottsched's account of physics is, as is to be expected, full of references to sources beyond Wolff – Gottsched is drawing on developments that were still unknown in time of Wolff's physical writings. Most of what Gottsched recounts feels nowadays very trite – like the account of Ptolemaic and Copernican systems and Kepler's discoveries – or then quite dated – like a theory that first chapter of Genesis describes a time when Earth was still not rotating and each day took one year, while the dust covering Earth's surface slowly flew away, first to reveal light and only couple of ”days” or years later the Sun and the Moon.
What is truly revolutionary in Wolffian setting is Gottsched's pneumatology, which contains, in addition to empirical and rational psychology, also natural theology (God is also, after all, a spirit). We might firstly note that by the time Gottsched was writing this work, Wolff had not yet published Latin versions of these themes. What is truly novel is not Gottsched's new arrangement of topics, but Gottsched's rejection of the pre-established harmony as the explanation of soul/body – interaction.
This development seems remarkable at first, but in some sense is quite natural. We've seen that Wolff moved to a position, in which the pre-established harmony had only a status of a likely hypothesis. Gottsched now suggests that if it at this stage all theories are mere hypothesis and none of them is truly certain, we should choose the option that is most familiar – that is, the theory of a true interaction between soul and body. The problem how souls as substances beyond world can have any effect on world as a closed series of causes and effects Gottsched solves easily through his earlier admission that souls are part of the world and thus the soul/body -interaction belongs to the natural course of events.
Gottsched's pneumatology thus shows a new tendency in Wolffian school. Furthermore, Gottsched wasn't even the only figure to do this. He explicitly refers to a study of one Martin Knutsen - best known as the teacher of Kant - in which the interaction was defended. But what did Wolff himself had to say about the topic? We shall see soon, as I am now about to embark on Wolff's rational psychology.
maanantai 25. elokuuta 2014
Such a perfect world
Wolff has attached
every entity with an essence, which, as it were, contains the kernel
of a thing or its central characteristics, from which all features of
the thing, or at least their possibility, can be explained. Every
thing, whether just possible or actual, has also an essence, or else
it wouldn't be a thing. Thus, even world must have such an essence or
nature, and the nature of the world (or simply nature) means for
Wolff the sum of all principles of mutation inherent in the world,
that is, the sum of all active forces in the world.
Now, by natural
Wolff simply means something belonging to the nature of any topic. In
case of world, natural then means something being or happening in
accordance with the forces and laws governing motion. Events that do
not happen according to these forces and laws are then supernatural
events or miracles. Furthermore, there is an intricate relation between the
miracles and laws of motion. Wolff admits that laws of motion are not
necessary and that events we would call miraculous are completely
possible events of another world. Yet, Wolff goes even
further and suggests that miracles can in a sense happen even during
the normal course of events – this doesn't imply contradiction,
Wolff says, but only the incompleteness of the world we live in. If
world is a clockwork, miracle is like a finger entering the works and
doing something clock itself wouldn't be able to do. Miracle changes
the world, and to do that, it must have adjusted the inner workings
of the elements of the world, because elements can exist only in a
single world. In order that the world would remain the same world,
another miracle will have to follow that changes everything back to
how it was.
Laws of motion then
define the nature of the world, but they also contribute to its
perfection. Perfection in general Wolff defined in his ontology as
arising from the unification of a multiplicity under some rules. In
case of world, this unification must take the form of a
spatio-temporal whole, and the rules governing it are clearly the
laws of motion. Thus, when we become aware of the laws governing
physical world or the order of nature, we are not just becoming more
informed, but also able to appreciate the perfection of the world.
Due to the incompleteness of human cognitive capacities, Wolff thinks
we can never know the perfection of the world completely – a clever
way for Wolff to avoid the possible objection that world does not
appear perfect.
Before I completely
move away from Wolff's cosmology, I would like to point out how
misleading is the Kantian account of what cosmology is about when it
comes to Wolff. As it is well known, Kant uses especially his idea of
antinomies to undermine the traditional cosmology – reason faces
insurmountable dilemmas in its most important questions. Now,
ironically the four problems Kant mentions are not treated by Wolff
in his cosmology. Problems about human freedom and possible creation
of the world are respectively psychological and theological for
Wolff, and the questions of the spatiotemporal limits of world and of
the divisibility of matter are never comprehensively discussed by
Wolff, as far as I can see.
Next time we'll turn
to Wolff's empirical psychology.
torstai 21. elokuuta 2014
Matter and forces
An important feature
of world, according to Wolff, is that it is a composite, that is, it
consists of parts. Some of these parts are familiar to us from
experience. Wolff points out that none of these experienced parts are
indivisible, but consist of further parts – we might call them in a
modern philosophical vocabulary middle-sized objects.
As composites, Wolff
continues, everyday worldly objects must be such that can be
completely explained through the structure and mutual relations of
these parts – in effect, they are machines similar to the world
itself. Because of the dependence, one need just change parts of a
middle-sized object in order to change the object itself. In fact,
this is the only way to truly have some effect on these objects.
All the changes on
the bodies require then moving some stuff from them or moving some
stuff in them – that is, movement or motion and direct physical
contact is an essential element in changes of the worldly objects. It
is then no wonder that a huge part of Wolff's cosmology is dedicated
to determining the so-called laws of motion – mostly descriptions of
what happens when several bodies collide with one another, depending
on their size, mass, velocity and cohesion. Although determining what
the correct laws of motion were was an ongoing philosophical and
scientific theme at least from the time of Descartes' Principia
philosophiae, I won't go
into any further details here, besides one exception.
The
one interesting element in the laws of motion is the notion that a
resting body will not by itself start to move and that a moving body
will not by itself change its velocity or direction. This property,
known nowadays as inertia, is called by Wolff a passive force of a
body, and according to him, should be taken as defining what is
called matter, which he takes
to be the extension of passive force.
With just matter, bodies would then just have stayed
in the same place for all eternity. The movement must have then been
generated by something else, that is, by an active force, which is
then transferred from one body to another in various collisions.
Matter
and active forces are then what one requires for explaining the
constitution of our world and
they might be taken as substances in what we observe of the world.
Yet, matter and
active forces are not the whole story. As I've mentioned in a previous text,
beyond the level of material bodies exists the level of elements of
bodies, because as composite entities material bodies must
ultimately consist of some simple entities. As simple, these elements
cannot have any extension and are therefore indivisible. They are not
like atoms are thought to be, Wolff says, because atoms are supposed
to have no true distinguishing qualities, which would contradict the
ontological principle that no two entities can have exactly same
qualities.
The differentiating
principle of the elements, Wolff suggests, should be their conatus,
that is, the basic force containing in nuce all the changes that will
happen to a particular element. In effect, elements are
differentiated by their whole life history. Because an essential part
of a life history of an element consists of its interactions with
other elements and these interactions are essential part of a nexus
forming a world, an element cannot exist except in a single world,
that is, by changing world you must change also its elements and vice
versa.
The actual relation
of elements to bodies is rather confusing in Wolffian philosophy.
What is clear is that elements constitute the realm of bodies we
observe. This means that many features we appear to observe in bodies
must be deceptive. For instance, bodies appear to consist of
continuous masses of such types of stuff as water. Yet, because all
matter and even water must consist of individual, indivisible and
completely distinct elements, they must actually be discontinuous.
What is unclear is how this phenomenal realm of continuities is
supposed to arise from true realm of discontinuities. The question is
muddled even more by corpuscles, which Wolff introduces as
constituting a level between observed bodies and elements. The
behaviour of bodies Wolff explains as constituted by the corpuscles,
parts of body, which still are divisible. Yet, no explanation is
given how corpuscles are generated from the level of elements, and
number of confusing questions remain. For instance, should a
corpuscle consist of an infinity of elements?
This enigma is a
point where we must leave the Wolffian concept of microcosm. Next
time I still have something to say about the order and perfection of
the world in Wolff's cosmology.
tiistai 19. elokuuta 2014
General cosmology (1731)
After Wolff's huge
works on logic and ontology, his Cosmologia generalis
feels refreshingly short with its under five hundred pages. The
shortness of the book might also reflect
its lack of importance in the purely philosophical part of Wolffian
system. Wolff's cosmology works mostly as an introduction to general
natural science or physics and is thus firmly connected with Wolff's
more empirical studies. Then again, of other parts of metaphysics
only theology is essentially said to be based on cosmology, because
Wolff argues for the existence of God from the existence of a certain
type of universe.
The
topic of Wolffian cosmology is then world or universe and general
types of objects in it. The very existence of universe is not so much
proven by pure reasoning,
but assumed – or at least the existence of a universe is justified
by certain empirical observations we have. What
we actually perceive or observe are certain things – rocks, trees,
houses and such. Now, all of
these entities are finite, that is, their existence requires a number
of other entities, either existing at the same time (like trunk
supports
branches) or existing before them (like rain requires gathering of
clouds).
![]() |
As they say, no smoke without fire. |
The
entities we observe are then connected to various other entities in
space and time through causal influences. These intricate relations
form a kind of web or nexus, in which one thing can be connected to
any other thing of the nexus through a string of causal relations. A
totality of such interconnected spatio-temporal things is then a world
or a universe. There might be different possible universes, because a
number of possible strings of events might have occurred, but only
one of them truly has occurred, that is, the string of events
constituting the history of our world.
I
have investigated the nature of this Wolffian universe in quite a
detail earlier,
but there's no harm in going through it all again. World is a
composite of things, and as a composite, its nature is dictated by
the nature of its parts. Thus, Wolff concludes, if we replaced just one peck of sand, the
world would be completely different, because its identity is
determined by the very entities constituting it.
Now,
in the actual universe,
all things we happen to
observe are composite substances, that is, they consist of other
things and what they are or their essence is determined by their
constituents. If we then want to change these substances, we must
essentially change their constitution, that is, remove some parts or
add other (for instance, if we want to make blackened metal objects
shiny, we must remove all the grime on the surface of the objects),
or then we can change the way they happen to move at the moment. All
these changes require then direct contact with the object to be
changed: you cannot pluck something out, if you are not close enough.
In effect, this means that world and all the composite objects that
we observe can be changed only through motion that comes in contact
with what is to be changed. Wolff can thus add that the world is like
a machine or a perfect watch which remains in action, even if its
creator fails to wind it.
As
we have mentioned number of times,
Wolff does not think that his account of world could be called
necessary in the strict sense of the word. Indeed, it is easy to see
that even if we could explain all the events of a current day, we
would be forced to explain them by referring all of them to past
events, which would then be completely unexplained and required a new
explanation. At the end, these events would be necessary in the
strict sense, only if no
other series of events would be even conceivable, which
is clearly not so.
Then
again, Wolff also claims that
worldy events are not completely inexplicable facts. Indeed,
this non-explicability of some facts
should be contradicted even by the principle of sufficient reason,
which states that all
contingent things and events arise out of some more primary things
and events. In case of universe, these primary things and events are
movements of material bodies, which with machine-like predictability
leads to further things and events. This deterministic view of
universe does not completely cancel the non-necessity of the worldly events, because a deterministic series as a whole is not necessitated by anything,
This is enough for
the Wolffian scheme of macrocosmos, next time I'll take a look of
what he has to say on microcosmos, that is, bodies and their parts.
keskiviikko 31. heinäkuuta 2013
Reduction of physics
At least since Aristotle's Posterior
analytics, mathematics has been the model of science, in which
everything should be deduced from self-evident axioms and
definitions. Indeed, mathematics was quite long considerably more
advanced and certain than any other field of research. It is then no
wonder that Descartes tried to fit physics and especially mechanics
into this model. Even more, he suggested that basic laws of mechanics
could be derived from mere geometrical considerations: after all,
matter was defined by extension, so the characteristics of the motion
of matter should be reducible to the extensional characteristics of
matter, such as size and velocity.
What Descartes had failed to take into
consideration was that the nature of matter is not exhausted by its
extension and that it cannot be identified with mere space. Thus, one
had to take into account also the mass of bodies, when considering
e.g. how two bodies behaved in a collision. Recognizing this made it
a necessity to empirically observe the actual movement of bodies and
to look for regularities that could be generalized from these
observations. Inconsistently, such studies were still often called
mathematical and even a semblance of mathematical deduction was
upheld.
Followers of Leibniz in Germany were
more aware of the inability to reduce physics to mathematics. Hence,
we see Christian Wolff admitting that his cosmological considerations
had an empirical basis and that reliable experiences in general must
supplement the inabilities of human understanding. In light of the
empiricist tendencies of Wolff, it is interesting to see that
Bilfinger supposed that it might be possible to derive basic laws of
physics apriorically. I do not think Bilfinger is necessarily going
against Wolff, but merely explicating the Wolffian position from a
different angle: true, in practice we must use empirical method, but
in principle we should be able to use deduction.
Bilfinger still doesn't advocate a
return to supposedly geometrical demonstrations of Descartes.
Instead, he supposes laws of physics should be derived from
metaphysics. In other words, Bilfinger doesn't want to state that
physical laws would be necessary like laws of logic and mathematics.
Instead, they are based ultimately on the decision of God. According
to the Wolffian position, God has created the best out of all the
possible worlds. Hence, all the laws that the world follows must also
be as perfect as they could be – and if we knew what is objectively
best, we could know the laws chosen by God.
What Bilfinger's position makes clear
is the contingency of physical laws. Specifically, the creator of the
laws still holds the power to suspend these laws for a limited period
and place. In common parlance such local suspensions of laws are
called miracles. In effect, Bilfinger is saying that miracles are
possible and that God has power to make them – another defense of
Wolff against suggestions of atheism.
So much for physical laws, next time I
shall deal with the difference between intuitive and symbolic
cognition.
tiistai 12. maaliskuuta 2013
Christian Wolff: Remarks on Reasonable thoughts on God, the world and the human soul, also on all things in general - Fragments of cosmology, rational psychology and natural theology
It has become evident that Wolff clearly
wants to distance himself from the image of a radical atheist and Spinozist.
This is even more evident, if we take into consideration his comments
on cosmology, which he straightforwardly defines as a discipline required
especially for the proof of God's existence. Indeed, it is the
contingency of the world and its dependence on God that Wolff
especially wants to emphasize in his comments – thus, he once again
uses considerable efforts to state the difference between absolute
and hypothetical necessity, which his opponents had muddled.
Wolff also clarifies the notion that
things are infinitely dependent on other things, which I also noted
to be somewhat confusing statement and which the pietists read as a
commitment to the eternity of the world. Wolff notes that he is
merely stating what the worldly things would have to be like, if only natural explanations or causation according to natural laws would be
allowed. In other words, there couldn't have been a natural beginning
of the world, because every natural law requires a previous state
from which the current state arose.
Such an impossibility does not of
course rule out a supernatural beginning or a beginning that did not
happen according to natural laws. Indeed, Wolff is convinced that the
principle of sufficient ground must then lead us to accept such a
supernatural beginning – infinite series of causes just isn't a
possibility. Wolff is here underlining the contingency of natural
laws: they are necessary only within the world, but not from a more
extensive perspective.
Furthermore, Wolff even makes it clear
that in a sense natural laws are not necessary even within the world,
that is, if God is taken into account. Wolff states that God need not
follow laws of nature, but if he so desires, he can make worldly
things behave in a manner they usually wouldn't. Of course, Wolff is
quick to point out that God doesn't do such miracles, unless there is a good
reason, but it is evident that he wants to make God's freedom stand
more out.
Interestingly, Wolff appears to take
the principle of the identity of indiscernibles as a mere natural
law. Indeed, he does consider it a real possibility that God could
have created two completely equal things, although he just has had no
reason to do it. We can see Wolff distancing himself here from
Leibniz, who apparently suggested that the identity of indiscernibles
might somehow be based on the principle of sufficient reason.
Even clearer is Wolff's struggle
against becoming identified a a mere Leibnizian in his behaviour
towards monadology. Wolff does want to present the theory of monads
in as plausible manner as possible, but he emphasizes forcefully
that he himself does not believe in it. Main reasons for his
disbelief are physical. Wolff is unconvinced that all the richness of
phenomena could be reduced to elements that all share the same force
of representation. True, one could on basis of this power understand
why elements or monads can form larger totalities, such a material
objects, but the further characteristic of material objects that resist the intrusion of other material objects into the same place is
something Wolff cannot understand as derived from force of
representation.
Still further clue of Wolff's growing
disenchanment of Leibniz is provided by Wolff's clarification of the
status of pre-established harmony as a mere hypothesis, but this is
something we have already dealt with. In addition, Wolff seems keen
to downplay the importance of whole rational psychology: if one just
knows e.g. that movements of soul and body somehow correspond with
one another, nothing more is required, if one does not have a
scientific bent for discovering grounds for everything.
The urge to distinguish himself from
Leibnizian thought is probably a symptom of Wolff's need to answer
the accusations of atheism and fatalism, which becomes even more
evident in the rest of Wolff's book. Thus, Wolff spends considerable
number of pages in explaining that while one can derive all
properties of souls from its representative capacities and all
properties of God from his capacity to view all possible worlds at
once, this does not mean that the nature of soul and God would be
mere theoretical or passive regard of actual and possible worlds, but
that both soul and God are active. And just like Wolff decided to
defend the freedom of the soul, equally certain is his tendency to
defend the divine liberty – even if the act of creating this world is
the most reasonable and God as eminently good and wise will then
inevitably choose to create it, this still doesn't mean that God
couldn't have chosen completely different world to create.
Thus end Wolff's remarks on his
metaphysics, which set his scheduled publication back a year – it
was only the next year that Wolff could finally publish his account
of biology, to which I shall turn next time.
Tunnisteet:
best of all possible worlds,
Christian Wolff,
cosmology,
God,
metaphysics,
monads,
natural theology,
psychology,
rational psychology,
soul,
world
keskiviikko 26. joulukuuta 2012
Johann Joachim Lange: Humble and detailed research of the false and corruptive philosophy in Wolffian metaphysical system on God, the world, and the men; and particularly of the so-called pre-established harmony of interaction between soul and body: as also in the morals based on such system: together with a historical preface on that what happened with its author in Halle: among treatises of many important matters, and with short check on remarks concerning duplicated doubts on Wolffian philosophy - Immaterial materialism
Wolff's deterministic view of the world
is essentially a materialistic doctrine, Lange thinks: immaterial
souls are free to act how they want and their existence should thus
make the world indeterministic. Now, Wolff does admit the existence
of souls without renouncing his determinism, and we shall see next
time how Lange reacts to this strategy.
In addition to souls, Lange sees
immaterialism playing a role already in Wolff's doctrine of world,
particularly in latter's notion of simple substances, which Lange
interprets as essentially identical with monads of Leibniz. This is
yet another point where Wolff himself is truly ambiguous. On the one
hand, Wolff does note the resemblance of his simple substances with
Leibnizian monads and does say that the simple substances in a sense
represent the world. On the other hand, Wolff prefers to speak of
elements and explains that representing is here symbolizing the interconnectedness of all things, because elements are not
literally conscious of anything.
Despite Wolff's skepticism of full
monadology, his doctrine of elements does satisfy some of Lange's
criteria for immaterialism or idealism. Material things, Lange says,
should be spatial and thus should be e.g. infinitely divisible, while
Wolffian elements are not spatial and definitely indivisible. Wolffian matter is thus based on immaterial things and is therefore a species of idealism, which Lange thinks is just as bad as materialism - Wolffian philosophy is then doubly bad, because it combines both idealism (in its doctrine of simple substances) and materialism (in its doctrine of deterministic world).
Lange
is clearly advocating the Aristotelian idea of matter as a
undifferentiated mass, which can be carved out into different shapes,
but which does not consist of independently existing units. While
Wolff does accept his own idea of matter without any proper
justification, Lange is equally stubborn and just states the
self-evidence of his views – matter just cannot consists of
something that is not matter. Lange would probably have been
horrified of the modern nuclear physics, which he would have had to
condemn as even more immaterial – matter consists there mostly of
void together with some small points without any determinate place.
Interestingly, Lange's criticism has
thus far dealt with questions that were later made famous by Kantian
antinomies. Lange believes that world had a specific beginning in
time and thinks that Wolff supposed it to be eternal; he holds
determinism to be broken by free actions of humans and God, while he
assumes Wolff to deny true freedom; and he believes matter to be
infinitely divisible, while Wolff supposed it to consist of
indivisible substances. Strikingly, Lange's anachronistic answer to
second antinomy was diametrically opposite to others, probably
because the doctrine of indivisible substances was associated with notorious atomism.
So much for Lange's views on Wolffian
cosmology, next time we'll see what he thinks of Wolffian psychology.
lauantai 22. joulukuuta 2012
Johann Joachim Lange: Humble and detailed research of the false and corruptive philosophy in Wolffian metaphysical system on God, the world, and the men; and particularly of the so-called pre-established harmony of interaction between soul and body: as also in the morals based on such system: together with a historical preface on that what happened with its author in Halle: among treatises of many important matters, and with short check on remarks concerning duplicated doubts on Wolffian philosophy - Stuck in a clockwork world
While Lange's interpretation of Wolff
in the question of the eternity of the world was at best
questionable, his view of Wolff and determinism is spot-on. Wolff
does believe that world – that is, an entity containing all complex
things – is governed by strict rules where the previous states of
things determine the further states of the things, just like in a
clock the current state of all the bits and pieces determines their
next state.
Lange's fear is that the strict
determinism of Wolffian world leaves no room for human freedom, or at
least it deprives from soul the possibility to control its body –
it is strictly speaking not I who lift my hand, but the movement of
the material objects in the vicinity of the hand. And if my hand
happens to strike body of a fellow soul – well, how could I be
accused, because the movement of the hand was necessary and people
cannot be punished for necessary actions. The judge could, of course,
retort that it is just as necessary for his mouth to utter the
condemning words, but still a lingering doubt is left – were truly
all these actions necessary?
Wolff's strategy would probably be to
deny the necessity of the world. After all, there are many different
possible worlds that God could have chosen to actualize and it is in
a sense contingent that he happened to pick out this world. Thus, it
is not necessary that I hit my neighbour, because in another possible
world I – or someone very similar to me – would not have stricken a man in similar circumstances.
Lange would be very unsatisfied with
this answer, and it all comes to how to define modalities like
necessity and contingency. Necessity Wolff speaks of Lange calls
geometric necessity, probably thinking of Spinoza's geometric method
– we might call it logical necessity. But it doesn't matter at all
to us, whether something happens in another possible world or not. It
is our own world we are interested of, and here everything happens
deterministically, that is, all the future states are determined once
the beginning has been given, without any possibility to actually
change the course of nature. This is the sense in which Lange wants
to speak of necessity – as the inevitability of events in the
context of the actual world. The respective contingency would then
not concern possibilities in another world, but indeterminacy of the
actual world.
Lange can then conclude that Wolff is
in this matter no better than Spinoza, who both rank as extreme
materialists. Wolff is in a sense even worse, because he is also an
extreme idealist. We shall see next time how this curious combination
is possible.
keskiviikko 19. joulukuuta 2012
Johann Joachim Lange: Humble and detailed research of the false and corruptive philosophy in Wolffian metaphysical system on God, the world, and the men; and particularly of the so-called pre-established harmony of interaction between soul and body: as also in the morals based on such system: together with a historical preface on that what happened with its author in Halle: among treatises of many important matters, and with short check on remarks concerning duplicated doubts on Wolffian philosophy (1724)
C. D. Broad's Examination of
McTaggart's philosophy is an example of how commentaries should
be made. Broad goes painstakingly through all the details and
intricacies of McTaggart's Nature of existence,
notes all the different variations that e.g. a theory of time might
have, considers fairly how McTaggart's own theory fairs and then
suggests the alternative he favours. Broad attempts to read
McTaggart's sometimes convoluted ideas in as clear and believable
manner as possible, sometimes agreeing with him, other times not.
Never is any statement of McTaggart discarded before an honest
consideration of what he attempts to say.
Then
there is the other type of commentary, where the opinions of the
commented author are assumed beforehand, ambiguous phrases and
passages are interpreted in the worst possible manner and generally
the author is treated like a customer of Spanish inquisition. Lange's
Bescheidene und ausführliche Entdeckung der falschen und
schädlichen Philosophie in dem Wolffianischen Systemate Metaphysico
von GOtt, der Welt, und dem Menschen; und insonderheit von der
sogenannten harmonia praestabilita des commercii zwischen Seel und
Leib: Wie auch in der auf solches Systema gegründeten Sitten-Lehre:
Nebst einem historischen Vorbericht, von dem, was mit dem Herrn
Auctore desselben in Halle vorgegangen: Unter Abhandelung vieler
wichtigen Materien, und mit kurzer Abfertigung der Anmerckungen über
ein gedoppeltes Bedencken von der Wolffianischen Philosophie: Nach
den principiis der gesunden Vernunft
falls into the latter category.
I cannot blame
Lange for a lack of thoroughness. On the contrary, he has read
through all of Wolff's major works published thus far and apparently
even some not as significant publications, and has left only his
logical work uncommented, because it doesn't significantly differ
from other contemporary books of logic. Lange has even found time to
read books of Wolff published in the same year as Lange's own title,
such as the book on teleology, I've just dealt with. It is not even
pretense of assuming axioms, which are far from evident that I find
fault with. This is just Lange playing with Spinoza's geometric
style, which is already familiar from an earlier work (Lange even
makes fun of Wolff, because he fails to present his theories in such
a format). What I found fault with was Lange's reading of Wolffian
philosophy,
The very first
”theorem” of Lange suggests that Wolff held onto the eternity of
the world. I found this rather surprising, because in reading Wolff I
had received the diametrically opposed impression that Wolff thought
world was not eternal. Problem lies with Wolff's ambiguity. On the
one hand, Wolff makes some remarks that appear to suggest that all
things are infinitely grounded on other things, that is, that there
has been an infinite series of events leading to this particular
moment of time. On the other hand, he also clearly states that world
is contingent and contingency is equivalent with non-eternity of the
world. We have then stumbled on a seeming contradiction in the
Wolffian system.
Lange's strategy in
avoiding the contradiction is to assume that Wolff is just trying to
sneak in the assumption of the eternity of the world and only pay lip service to the idea of creation, thus making the hypothesis of a
creator superfluous. I, on the contrary, try to take seriously
Wolff's explicit commitment to the non-eternity of the world. True,
the references to infinite grounding remain problematic, but I
consider the meaning of these passages to be more uncertain. I can
accept the idea that Wolff might have toyed with the idea of an
eternal world, but left the question purposefully ambiguous.
Furthermore, I might also assume that the infinite grounding means
just the fact that any thing in Wolffian world is supposed to be in a
necessary relation with all the other denizens of a spatially
infinite world.
In addition to
finding fault in Lange's interpretation of Wolff, I also question his
assumption that the acceptance of an eternally existing world would
necessarily lead to atheism. This conclusion holds only if the
creation is supposed to happen with time, as the first event of the
world. The assumption completely ignores the possibility that the
creation happened outside time, which would still allow the eternity
of the world. Lange's assumption makes God not just personal, but
almost a worldly thing – God is like a lead programmer of an
interactive netgaming world, who actively takes part in the events by
using the powers of moderator. The supposedly Wolffian God, on the
other hand, is like a programmer who knows he has done so good work
that he never needs to do anything to improve it. This doesn't mean
that this second type of God would be e.g. incapable of miracles –
they would just be like preprogammed Easter eggs that bend the rules
of the game when players stumbled onto right coordinates.
We'll continue with
Lange's criticism on Wolffian cosmology with the notion of
determinism.
sunnuntai 8. tammikuuta 2012
Christian Wolff: Reasonable thoughts on God, world, and human soul, furthermore, of all things in general - World as a clockwork
You might think that after a chapter on
empirical psychology Wolff would turn into rational psychology, that
is, that he would explain what has been observed of human
consciousness. Yet, a chapter on cosmology or the study of world
intervenes with the pretext that knowing the essence of human soul
requires knowing the essence of the world.
The basic structure of the world Wolff
discovers through observation: world is a series of variable things
that exist side by side one another (i.e. in space) and one after
another (i.e. in time) and generally are connected to one another in
the sense that anyone of the things contains a reason why the others
near it in space and time are situated as they are. World is then a
complex thing, that is, a thing consisting of things that are parts
of the world.
The notion of a complex thing is
familiar already from Wolffian ontology, and indeed, most of what
Wolff finds characteristic of the world is a simple application of
previous ontological results. Thus, world as a complex is defined by
being a certain combination of its parts, like a structure built out
of Lego blocks. Yet, the temporality of the world ensures that it is
not a mere static structure, but processual, and indeed, its later
states are based on nothing else but its previous states. The world
is then like a machine – and Wolff specifically compares it to a
clockwork, where the position of the hand is determined by its
earlier positions and by the movement of the machinery.
World is then for Wolff deterministic
and all events in the world are certain, if the previous events are
known. Yet, this does not mean that the events would be necessary:
they could have happened otherwise. Analogically, there is not just
one possible way to make a clock, but the parts could have been
assembled differently. True, we don't see any alternative worlds
lying around, like we do see clocks of various sorts, but we can read
alternative world histories in works of fiction. Wolff is here
applying the idea of possible worlds, which he has probably picked
from Leibniz.
The assumption of possible worlds
creates doubles of the modalities of necessity and possibility.
Firstly, we could speak of absolute possibility and necessity, that
is, of what is possible or necessary in all possible worlds.
Secondly, we could speak of possibility and necessity within one
possible world: what is possible in this sense is something that has
happened, happens or will happen in this particular world. What is
specifically impossible in one possible world are the events of all
the other possible worlds. The possible worlds contradict then one
another: only one of them can be actual, no matter what David Lewis
says.
As any philosophy student should know,
the idea of possible worlds was important for Leibniz as a component
in the justification of the perfection of the actual world: God knew
all the possible worlds and as a wise and good person chose the best
possible world to be actualised. We are still at a chapter on
cosmology and God will be investigated only later on. Still, Wolff
prepares the issue by characterising the notion of the perfection of
a world.
Wolff begins by noting that all complex
things and thus all worlds have some sort of regularity and are
therefore valuable: remember that in the chapter on ontology Wolff
had defined perfection through regularity. Yet, worlds are not all of
same value, Wolff adds: some are more regular than others. By
regularity Wolff does not mean a mere uniformity, which by itself
would not mean perfection. Instead, diversity is also an essential
component in perfection. In other words, the value of the world is to
be decided by the question what sort of laws it has: a good world
follows a number of laws, all of which form a rational hierarchy.
Note that Wolff does not intend that we could deduce what these laws
could be. Instead, one finds the particular laws through abstraction
from the actual phenomena and more general laws through abstraction
from more general laws. In this manner Wolff justifies the general
law that nature makes no leaps.
The possible worlds are nowadays
treated as a legitimate way to explain e.g. modal properties of
sentences. Yet, Wolff's manner of suggesting a scheme for the
perfection of the world is rather unbelievable, because there are a
number of possible scales for measuring the perfection of anything.
The problem can be better grasped through the analogy of clockworks.
There are rather different types of
clocks and watches, although the main principle and purpose is the
same for all of them. Now, while one clock might beat the others by
being more realiable and always on time – say, some atomic clock –
another clock might be cheaper, although not as precise as a time
keeper. Then again, a fancy pocket watch might not be cheap nor
reliable, at least if its owner forgets to wind it, but it still is
ecological, requiring no batteries, and probably the most sylish of
the three examples. It would be rather difficult – if not downright
impossible – to say which of the three clocks is the most perfect:
all of them are good in some respect and bad in other respects.
It appears reasonable to suppose that
the perfection of possible worlds would be similarly and most likely
even more multidimensional: that is, there would be no single
criteria for deciding the perfection of the world, but several.
Hence, although one world might perfect according to one criterion,
another world could well be perfect according to another criterion.
How should one then choose between them?
True, the Leibnizian-Wolffian God might
have some clever mathematical formula that would take into account
all the different aspects of perfection and hence be a perfect
criteria for deciding between several possible worlds. The problem
with this solution is that one should still demonstrate that this
clever formula could not give the same value to two different
possible worlds: otherwise, the possibility of two equally good
worlds would still remain. We shall see later if Wolff has any
argument to support this claim.
So much for macrocosm, next time we
shall visit the opposite context or the microcosm.
Tilaa:
Blogitekstit (Atom)