Concepts of simple and complex substances were of great interest to Wolffians, being one of the primary divisions of substances, and Crusius seems eager to show where Wolffians wen’t wrong with them. He firstly notes that just like the concepts of part and whole, on which the two former concepts are based on, can actually mean very different things. Starting with the parts, these can mean, Crusius says, any group of things we can represent as forming also a one thing, which then is the respective whole. Furthermore, these parts can be actual or such that they can be separated elsewhere than in our thoughts, but they can also be mere thought parts, which can be distinguished in our thinking, but not really separated.
Simple is then for Crusius something that has no parts - in some sense, while complex is something that has parts - again, in some sense. Since the notion of parts was already twofold, this same duality continues with the notions of simple and complex: something may be simple or complex just based on mere thoughts, but also based on something outside our thought.
Even in case of actual simplicity, Crusius notes, there are various levels of simplicity. The epitome of simplicity, he thinks, is God, who is not just a simple substance - that is, something, which cannot be separated into further substances - but also has a simple essence in the sense that no property could be removed from his essence. This is not always the case, Crusius says, because substance can be simple, like a human soul, without having a simple essence. Even a complex substance, like air, Crusius notes, is simpler than, say, a human body, because the former has only integral parts - parts that all have the same essence - but no physical parts - parts that have a different essence from one another.
Crusius also notes that it is a different thing, if something is simple as such or has nothing separable in it, than if something is simple on the condition that the current world exists, Crusius notes that we cannot really distinguish between the two cases and neither can any finite being, but God might be able to do it.
Every force is in some subject, Crusius insists, because no subjectless forces could be thought of. On this basis Crusius argues that in case of complex substances, their force must be determined by forces of their parts. Crusius then concludes that if a complex substance wouldn’t ultimately consist of simple substances, the constituent forces would have no immediate subject where to subsist, which he thinks is absurd. Despite the seeming complexity of the argument, it appears to just assume what it sets out to prove: that the existence of a complex thing must be based on the existence of simple things.
Crusius is especially keen to distance his notion of a simple substance from a mathematical understanding of simplicity. Mathematics, he says, considers only abstract magnitudes, not other determinations of things. In other words, he rephrases, mathematics is only about the concept of space and its possible divisions. Thus, it was natural for mathematicians to assume the existence of points, which should have even no parts that could be thought of as being outside one another. Yet, Crusius states, no true simple substance is simple in the mathematical sense, but is spatial - they just cannot be physically divided further.
Crusius goes thus straight against the Wolffian notion of elements, which are more like non-spatial forces. If we would accept such non-spatial substances, how could we account for spatial matter being generated from them, especially as any concrete matter would require an infinite amount of them? Furthermore, he continues, we couldn’t even say how such pointlike substances could touch one another, as there are always further points between any two points.
Näytetään tekstit, joissa on tunniste complex things. Näytä kaikki tekstit
Näytetään tekstit, joissa on tunniste complex things. Näytä kaikki tekstit
tiistai 12. heinäkuuta 2022
tiistai 24. huhtikuuta 2018
Joachim Darjes: Elements of metaphysics 1 - Building bodies
Ever since Descartes suggested that matter is defined by extension, philosophers had been proposing theories as to what Cartesian idea of matter had overlooked, since clearly, extension as such is not yet matter. Darjes enters this discussion in the section on somatology, or theory of bodies or composite entities. He notes that to make a set of multiple entities into a unified entity, it isn't enough just to put them together. Instead, these parts must also cohere with one another.
Now, as we saw in the previous post, Darjes thought that in order that entities can cohere, all of those entities must be non-spontaneous, but also some of them must be active. In other words, there are no completely passive bodies in Darjesian metaphysics, only more or less active. The level of activity in bodies can even be perceived, Darjes suggests, since the difference of fluids and solids reduces to it – fluid bodies have more active entities in them than solid bodies, which have only so much active entities as required for the sake of coherence. Since the difference between fluids and solids is ultimately based on the essential difference between active and passive entities, the difference between fluids and solids must also be essential, Darjes concludes. Somewhat surprisingly, this means that fluids cannot really change into solids or vice versa.
A significant part of philosophical treatises of corporeal objects from this period often include an account of simple mechanical interactions, in which two bodies collide with one another. Darjes is no exception to this rule. He considers several cases – what if only one is moving or both, what if colliding bodies are solids or fluids etc. We need not get too far into the details, but just to note the general attempt to determine the result of the collision from the constituents and the structure of the colliding bodies. For instance, in a collision between a solid and a fluid, the fluid gives away, because a fluid body has more active constituents, which will move according to their own drive, as soon as bonds of coherence holding them together loosen a little bit, while the solid can remain unified in an easier manner.
As a final part of the first tome of his metaphysics Darjes introduces a discipline called mechanology, a study of machines. Machines, for Darjes, are systems of non-spontaneous entities, in which systems, again, mean collections of entities that can affect one another. Systems and therefore also machines are to be clearly differentiated from cohering bodies – in a system, the constituting bodies do not form a single entity, but remain independent of one another. Darjesian understanding of machines is quite extensive – the constituting parts of machines can be solid or fluid bodies or theoretically even elements. Indeed, the whole mechanology remains on a quite general level, where Darjes finds out such revelatory truths as that the state of a machine depends on its previous state.
The second tome of Darjes metaphysics moves then to the investigation of soul, which shall also be the topic of my next post.
Now, as we saw in the previous post, Darjes thought that in order that entities can cohere, all of those entities must be non-spontaneous, but also some of them must be active. In other words, there are no completely passive bodies in Darjesian metaphysics, only more or less active. The level of activity in bodies can even be perceived, Darjes suggests, since the difference of fluids and solids reduces to it – fluid bodies have more active entities in them than solid bodies, which have only so much active entities as required for the sake of coherence. Since the difference between fluids and solids is ultimately based on the essential difference between active and passive entities, the difference between fluids and solids must also be essential, Darjes concludes. Somewhat surprisingly, this means that fluids cannot really change into solids or vice versa.
A significant part of philosophical treatises of corporeal objects from this period often include an account of simple mechanical interactions, in which two bodies collide with one another. Darjes is no exception to this rule. He considers several cases – what if only one is moving or both, what if colliding bodies are solids or fluids etc. We need not get too far into the details, but just to note the general attempt to determine the result of the collision from the constituents and the structure of the colliding bodies. For instance, in a collision between a solid and a fluid, the fluid gives away, because a fluid body has more active constituents, which will move according to their own drive, as soon as bonds of coherence holding them together loosen a little bit, while the solid can remain unified in an easier manner.
As a final part of the first tome of his metaphysics Darjes introduces a discipline called mechanology, a study of machines. Machines, for Darjes, are systems of non-spontaneous entities, in which systems, again, mean collections of entities that can affect one another. Systems and therefore also machines are to be clearly differentiated from cohering bodies – in a system, the constituting bodies do not form a single entity, but remain independent of one another. Darjesian understanding of machines is quite extensive – the constituting parts of machines can be solid or fluid bodies or theoretically even elements. Indeed, the whole mechanology remains on a quite general level, where Darjes finds out such revelatory truths as that the state of a machine depends on its previous state.
The second tome of Darjes metaphysics moves then to the investigation of soul, which shall also be the topic of my next post.
perjantai 11. joulukuuta 2015
Baumgarten: Metaphysics – Kinds of substances
The primary
classification of things in metaphysical treatises has long been that
of substances and accidences and Baumgarten's Metaphysics makes no
exception. Substances are things that can exist without being
attached to something else, while accidences have to exist in
something else, namely, in substances. Furthermore, Baumgarten adds,
accidences are not just something externally connected to a
substance, but a substance must contain some reason why such
accidences exist within it. In other words, substance is a force that
in a sense causes its accidences – if completely, they are its
essentials and attributes, if partially, they are its modes.
Now, substances with
modes are variable or they have states, which can change into other
states.
Like all
things in Baumgarten's system, these changes also require grounding
in some forces. Changes effected by forces are then activities of
substances having these forces. Such activities might be connected
with changes in the active substance itself, but they might also link
to changes in other things: these other things then have a passion.
In latter case, the forces might act alone to produce a certain
effect and then we speak of real actions and passions, or then the
passive substance also has some activity at the same time as it has
passions, and then we speak of ideal actions and passions. The
division of real and ideal actions and passions is of importance in
relation to Baumgarten's thoughts about causality.
Because all
substances have forces, all of them have also activities – if
nothing else, then at least activities towards themselves.
Furthermore, activity does not define just the essence of substances,
but also their mutual presence – substances are present to one
another, Baumgarten says, when they happen to interact with one
another.
Baumgarten divides
substances, in quite a Wolffian manner, into complex and simple
substances (Baumgarten does admit that we can also have complexes of
accidences, but these are of secondary importance in comparison with
complexes of substances). Not so Wolffian is Baumgarten's endorsement
of Leibnizian term ”monad” as the name of the ultimate simple
substances. Rounding up the division of substances is the division of
simple substances into finite and infinite substances, in which
infinite substance has all the positive properties in highest grade
and thus exists necessarily and immutably – this is something we
will return to in Baumgarten's theology – while finite substances
change their states and have restrictions.
This concludes
Baumgarten's account of the substances or primary entities of the
world, and like with Wolff, we can already discern the outlines of
the three concrete metaphysical disciples. But before moving away
from ontology, we still have to discuss Baumgarten's account of basic
relations of entities.
tiistai 19. elokuuta 2014
General cosmology (1731)
After Wolff's huge
works on logic and ontology, his Cosmologia generalis
feels refreshingly short with its under five hundred pages. The
shortness of the book might also reflect
its lack of importance in the purely philosophical part of Wolffian
system. Wolff's cosmology works mostly as an introduction to general
natural science or physics and is thus firmly connected with Wolff's
more empirical studies. Then again, of other parts of metaphysics
only theology is essentially said to be based on cosmology, because
Wolff argues for the existence of God from the existence of a certain
type of universe.
The
topic of Wolffian cosmology is then world or universe and general
types of objects in it. The very existence of universe is not so much
proven by pure reasoning,
but assumed – or at least the existence of a universe is justified
by certain empirical observations we have. What
we actually perceive or observe are certain things – rocks, trees,
houses and such. Now, all of
these entities are finite, that is, their existence requires a number
of other entities, either existing at the same time (like trunk
supports
branches) or existing before them (like rain requires gathering of
clouds).
![]() |
As they say, no smoke without fire. |
The
entities we observe are then connected to various other entities in
space and time through causal influences. These intricate relations
form a kind of web or nexus, in which one thing can be connected to
any other thing of the nexus through a string of causal relations. A
totality of such interconnected spatio-temporal things is then a world
or a universe. There might be different possible universes, because a
number of possible strings of events might have occurred, but only
one of them truly has occurred, that is, the string of events
constituting the history of our world.
I
have investigated the nature of this Wolffian universe in quite a
detail earlier,
but there's no harm in going through it all again. World is a
composite of things, and as a composite, its nature is dictated by
the nature of its parts. Thus, Wolff concludes, if we replaced just one peck of sand, the
world would be completely different, because its identity is
determined by the very entities constituting it.
Now,
in the actual universe,
all things we happen to
observe are composite substances, that is, they consist of other
things and what they are or their essence is determined by their
constituents. If we then want to change these substances, we must
essentially change their constitution, that is, remove some parts or
add other (for instance, if we want to make blackened metal objects
shiny, we must remove all the grime on the surface of the objects),
or then we can change the way they happen to move at the moment. All
these changes require then direct contact with the object to be
changed: you cannot pluck something out, if you are not close enough.
In effect, this means that world and all the composite objects that
we observe can be changed only through motion that comes in contact
with what is to be changed. Wolff can thus add that the world is like
a machine or a perfect watch which remains in action, even if its
creator fails to wind it.
As
we have mentioned number of times,
Wolff does not think that his account of world could be called
necessary in the strict sense of the word. Indeed, it is easy to see
that even if we could explain all the events of a current day, we
would be forced to explain them by referring all of them to past
events, which would then be completely unexplained and required a new
explanation. At the end, these events would be necessary in the
strict sense, only if no
other series of events would be even conceivable, which
is clearly not so.
Then
again, Wolff also claims that
worldy events are not completely inexplicable facts. Indeed,
this non-explicability of some facts
should be contradicted even by the principle of sufficient reason,
which states that all
contingent things and events arise out of some more primary things
and events. In case of universe, these primary things and events are
movements of material bodies, which with machine-like predictability
leads to further things and events. This deterministic view of
universe does not completely cancel the non-necessity of the worldly events, because a deterministic series as a whole is not necessitated by anything,
This is enough for
the Wolffian scheme of macrocosmos, next time I'll take a look of
what he has to say on microcosmos, that is, bodies and their parts.
maanantai 28. huhtikuuta 2014
Complex extension
A clear difference between Wolff's
Latin and German books of philosophy is that the more extensive Latin
books have also a more detailed structure than their German
counterparts. This is also true of Latin ontology. The book began
with a section detailing the two basic principles of contradiction
and sufficient reason. The second section was then dedicated to
explicating the central notion of essence and some related concepts.
Finally, the third section dealt with several characteristics common
to all entities, such as identity, quantity and truth. Together,
these three sections then formed the first part of Wolff's ontology,
dealing with things in general.
The second and final part of Wolffian
ontology is then about a general classification of things into simple
and complex things. The second part contains, quite naturally, one
section dedicated to complex entities and another dedicated to simple
entities. In addition to these, there's also a section investigating
relations between things, probably just because there was no better
place for it.
![]() |
Schematics of Wolff's Latin ontology |
Wolff does not add considerable
novelties to his account of complex entities in German metaphysics –
the important fact is that the essence of a complex or composite
entity is based on the essences of its parts and their mutual
relations. Parts are then more essential than their combinations, in
which they still retain their independence.
Now, when we are conscious of such a
combination of several mutually extrinsic things, we see the
combination as extended. In fact, we can abstract from all other
features of the complex things, but this extension, as we do in
geometry. Geometrically we can then define such notions as continuity
(when you cannot put anything else between any two parts of a single
thing) and contiguity (when you cannot put anything between surfaces
of two different things). If two things are not contiguous, one can
also define distance as the shortest line between them.
Extension and related notions can then
be used to define space. As I've said earlier, Wolff follows Leibniz
in accepting the idea of a relational nature of space – space is
determined by certain relations between extended objects (distance
etc.), so that space wouldn't exist without extended things having
those relations. Here Wolff goes even so far to say that absolute
space is just a useful fiction that we abstract from the concrete
relations of complex things – and same goes for absolute time.
A novelty in Wolff's treatment of space
and time in comparison with German metaphysics is that he extends his
account to motion. On the one hand, this means just an extension of
mathematical treatment of space or extended things to moving things.
Lines can be used to describe not just extension, but also motion –
Wolff is here expounding basics of vector calculation.
On the other hand, Wolff also suggests
that if both absolute space and time are fictions, so must absolute
motion be at least partially fictitious. Still, he is not willing to
say that motion is completely imaginary. What is imaginary is the
idea of motion happening in some absolute coordinate system with
fixed places. Instead, motion is just change in the relations of
things – a falling ball is, say, coming closer to the ground.
Furthermore, movement is something
that is sustained by the moving entity – falling ball has impetus
for moving in constant velocity towards the ground. In addition
relations to external things can change the status of movement a
thing has – a ball is constantly accelerated by something in its
fall, and once it has hit the ground, it will stop moving towards the
ground.
So much for complex things and their
characteristics, next time I'll have something to say about simple
things.
maanantai 30. heinäkuuta 2012
Christian Wolff: Reasonable thoughts on the effects of nature (1723) and Ludwig Philipp Thümmig: Attempt to most thoroughly clarify the most remarkable incidents in nature, whereby one will be lead to the deepest understanding of them (1723)
Baroque Cycle of Neal Stephenson
contains a lovely scene portraying a typical meeting of the Royal
Society. A number of curios and weird phenomena are presented to the
audience without any regulated order – one members tells a story of
fying fishes living in some oceans, another describes a neat trick
with a vacuum pump, while third has just developed differential
calculus.
Although such a motley of topics seems
chaotic, it reveals what has truly captivated the hearts of men for
science – it is the extraordinary that interests us. Consideration
of curiosities has for long been a part of science – there is even
a pseudo-Aristotelian book Problems,
which is nothing more than a collection of what the author considered
weird and proposed explanations for these dilemmas. Nowadays weird has been used for
good measure in popularisation of science – for instance, in the
show Mythbusters
dealing with such age-old problems as whether cars truly explode when
driven off cliffs.
Versuch
einer gründlichen Erläuterung der merckwürdigsten Begebenheiten
in der Natur, wodurch man zur innersten Erkenntnis derselben
geführet wird
is a similar collection of curios, written by Ludvig Philip Thümmig,
whom we have already met as an editor of a book of Wolffian essays. Here we finally see some of Thümmig's own work, as he ponders such
scientific problems as why a boy sees everything double, why animals with two bodies combined are sometimes born, why some trees grow from their
leaves and why does gravity work in different grades across the globe
– Thümmig's solution to this question convinced at least his
mentor Wolff, who mentions it in his own book on natural science,
Vernünfftige
Gedancken von den Würckungen der Natur,
which is also the second book I am considering this time.
While
Thümmig's book is a haphazard motley, Wolff does not fail to give us
a work with systematically arranged topics. Here Wolff is once again
just following a far older tradition. The nameless collector of the
works of Aristotle arranged his books on nature in the following
order: first came books on the general principles of natural world,
then followed books on the cosmos in general and the heavens in
particular, after which came books on atmospheric phenomena and
earthly objects, while the story finished with books on living nature.
This formal scheme was so well thought out that even Hegel
essentially followed it in his own philosophy of nature. Thus, it is
no wonder that Wolff himself applied this often used model of natural
science.
In
his natural science or physics Wolff is quite reliant on empirical
information and rarely wonders from presenting the conclusions of the
science of his time. One exception where Wolff's physics comes in
contact with his metaphysics is the description of animal sensation,
where Wolff reminds us of the Leibnizian idea of pre-established harmony: while human bodies go through certain changes in their
sensory organs, their souls have corresponding sensations, although
bodies and souls do not interact with one another.
A
more detailed crossing of physics and metaphysics occurs in the very
beginning of the work, in the description of the physical objects as
complex substances. An important conclusion of this definition is
according to Wolff that all the properties of the complex should be
derived from the properties of its constituents and the
spatiotemporal structure according to which these constituents have
been combined - I have called this the lego-block view of the world. Although seemingly innocent, endorsing this view leads
Wolff to some substantial consequences.
Observations
suggest that there are some peculiar properties that are difficult to
explain through mere spatiotemporal structure of things – for
instance, the characteristic of objects gravitating toward the
nearest big collection of matter or the property of warmth. Now, if these characteristics are not
explainable through the spatiotemporal form of the bodies, it must be
explained through the constituents of them – that is, there must be
types of matter that cause gravitation or warmth.
The
assumption of special matters was not a peculiarity of Wolff, but a
common occurence at the time, and even Hegel commented on this habit
of scientists. One just saw a peculiar phenomenon – certain kinds
of metal attract or repel one another – which was explained by
assuming a new type of matter, in this case magnetic matter. While
the notion of caloric or heat matter and similar properties as matters sound rather quaint, we
should not assume that such reification of properties is non-existent
nowadays. One just has to open a book on particle physics to learn
about photons or particles of electro-magnetism, glueons or the
particles holding the nucleus of atoms together and perhaps even gravitons causing gravitation.
Physicists
may well have good reasons for such reification in these cases, but
taken to its extremes it will lead to the philosophical theory of
tropes – all general properties are actually individual things,
like this redness, this sweetness, this roundness. The individual
things are then just mere conglomerate of these tropes – for
instance, the three tropes of particular sweetness, redness and
roundness combine to form a particular strawberry.
The
setback of trope theories is that it is difficult to see how all
properties could be reified. For instance, do not the tropes
themselves have properties, such as being a trope? Is this then
supposed to be yet another trope? Furthermore, a trope theorist has
difficulties explaining how to account of our thinking about universals.
Redness of this particular strawberry should in trope theory be
completely different from redness of this particular flag – how can
then we describe both of them as red? If we suppose that the two
tropes are connected by being similar in some manner, we face yet
another dilemma – isn't the similarity yet another property?
So
much for the physics of Wolffians. Next time I shall discuss the
first of many atheism controversies to come.
perjantai 27. tammikuuta 2012
Christian Wolff: Reasonable thoughts on God, world, and human soul, furthermore, of all things in general - Can soul be material?
While in the chapter on empirical
psychology Wolff merely observed the mental capacities of human
beings, in the chapter on rational psychology he tries to determine
the nature of the soul or the thing that has such capacities.
Nowadays it is easy to think such an attempt as completely
ridiculous: after all, Kant should have shown that rational
psychology was based on mere sophistic reasoning. We shall have to
speak of the Kantian criticism in the future. At this point we may
just note the surprising fact that Wolffian theory of the soul begins
with a reasoning of transcendental nature. That is, Wolff begins from
the fact that human beings are conscious of themselves and
investigates the presuppositions of this fact.
The beginning of Wolff's reasoning is
innocent enough. We are conscious of something, Wolff says, when we
can distinguish it from other things. For instance, I am conscious of
a hand mirror, only if I am able to differentiate the mirror from
e.g. hands holding it. Particularly, consciousness of oneself implies
the capacity to distinguish between oneself and other things. In
other words, consciousness is connected with a clarity of thoughts,
which for Wolff meant a capacity to distinguish the object of thought
from other objects.
Furthermore, in order to distinguish
different objects from one another and to recognise them as
different, one must be able to contrast them with one another and to
consider them one after another, Wolff continues. In order to do
this, the conscious being must have imagination and memory, that is,
he must be able to think of things that are not present and to
recognise them as having been present. Indeed, consciousness is
generated, because we can think of a thought for a period of time,
note that the time has changed, but the thought itself has remained.
The arguments thus far have been
essentially about characterising what it means to be a conscious
personality: e.g. a person needs to have a memory, in order that she
would have a sense of continuity of self. I cannot see why Kant or
his followers would have any reason to argue with these
considerations. In fact, much of the Kantian and post-Kantian German
philosophy consists of such theorising on the nature of human
consciousness, although in a somewhat deeper level.
What Kant and his followers would
probably find unacceptable is the next move where Wolff tries to
prove the immateriality of soul or the thing that is conscious. Wolff
starts by noting that all material processes must be explicable
through mere mechanical movement of material objects. Thus, if soul
would be material, thinking would also be such a mechanical process.
Now, human beings can be conscious of their own thinking, that is,
they can note that the starting and the end point of thinking are
different and still parts of a continuous process of one thing. Here
Wolff simply states that such representation of continuity is
impossible with mere matter: material objects as complexes can at
best represent only other complexes, but they cannot represent a
unified process of thought.
Wolff's blunt statement that matter as
a mechanism cannot represent thought processes is quite
unsatisfactory, especially as we nowadays don't think that matter
consists merely of lego-like blocks that interact only through
mechanical contact. Wolff does try to amend his reasoning by noting
that material object can represent things – for instance, we can make a clay model of a building – but it cannot represent the
original as separate from the representation. I have a feeling that
Wolff has here confused first- and third-person perspectives. Surely
an external observer cannot see e.g. brain as a representation of the
process of thought,but this does not mean that the brain could not
represent this to itself, if it just were conscious.
The situation appears even worse, when
we consider that by denying the complexity of the soul Wolff has to
accept the possibility of a simple thing representing complexities,
which appears at least as difficult as a complex representing a
unity. Indeed, how could a single partless entity represent a complex
of many entities correctly? The only possibility appears to be that
the complex is characterised through passage of time: at one point
soul represents one part of the complex, at another point other parts
and at final point the combination of the two previous phases.
Indeed, we might well believe that human consciousness does work in
this manner: e.g. when looking at a boat moving at the sea, we
concentrate first on its rear end and then on the other end and only
after that note that both parts go together.
The problem with this solution is that
it once again threatens the supposed unity of consciousness. Suppose
that I am thinking of myself. This act of thinking then represents
some state of my mind, say, a memory of yesterday. But this act as
simple can only represent one thing, thus, it cannot represent
itself. We could then begin a new act of thinking that had the
original act as its object. This procedure could be iterated
indefinitely and so a problem is revealed: no matter how far we'd go,
there would always be left at least one act of thought that had not
been combined with other acts, that is, the very act of thinking
all the other thoughts. This problematic was something that intrigued
some of the later German philosophers, although Wolff appears to not have noticed it.
Wolff's argument for the immateriality
of the soul was then unconvincing. Next time we shall see whether he
can at least characterise this supposed immaterial entity.
perjantai 18. marraskuuta 2011
Christian Wolff: Reasonable thoughts on God, world, and human soul, furthermore, of all things in general - Lego block view of the world
System builders do love to divide
things into two classes (unless they are German idealists and
probably more into threefold divisions). Wolff follows this tradition
and distinguishes between simple and complex things. (By the way, one
just has to appreciate German language for its capacity to make such
important concepts easy to grasp. Simple things are ”einfache”,
which could be translated as ”one-folded” - simple thing has but
one part. Complex things, on the other hand, are ”zusammengesetzt”
or ”put together” out of smaller things. English equivalents are
less transparent.)
How does Wolff then justify his
division? The existence of the complex or assembled objects he
accepts as given in our experience: the things outside us can be seen
to consist of smaller things. In addition to being assembled of other
things, complex things have various other characteristic properties:
- complex things have a magnitude (after all, they consist of many things)
- complex things fill space and are shaped in some manner
- complex things can be enlarged or diminished and the order of their parts can be varied without changing anything essential
- complex things can be generated by putting things together, and they can be destroyed by separating the constituents
- the existence of the complex things is always contingent
- the generation of complex things takes time and is humanly intelligible
Simple things, on the other hand,
cannot be found in the experience, Wolff says, so their existence
must be deduced. Here Wolff invokes the principle of the sufficient
reason: the existence of a complex thing cannot be explained
completely, unless there is some final level of things from which the
complex thing has been assembled. These simple things have then
characteristics completely different from the complex things:
- simple things do not have any magnitude
- simple things do not fill space nor do they have any figure
- simple things cannot change their internal constitution (because they do not have one)
- simple things cannot be assembled from other things nor can they be disassembled; they can only be generated ”at a single blow” (einmahl)
- simple things are either necessary or generated through something necessary
- the generation of simple things is atemporal and non-intelligible to humans
Wolff's scheme reminds one probably of
atomism, yet, atoms have usually not been described as non-spatial: in this Wolff's simple things resemble Leibnizian
monads. Yet, if we ignore for now the nature of space, which I shall
be discussing next time, we can discern a common pattern shared by
atomism, Leibnizian monadology and Wolffian ontology of simple and
complex things.
This pattern is based on the idea that
world is like a game with legos. There are magnificient buildings and
vehicles, but they are all made out of small objects – lego blocks
– which in themselves cannot be broken down to smaller pieces. No
complex of legos is necessary and you can even see the revealing
lines that tell how to disassemble a ten-story castle into individual
blocks. Indeed, in all the various combinations, lego blocks remain
distinct individuals that just happen to be attached together.
The lego block view of the world is so
common these days that it is difficult to remember other
possibilities. It was different with Aristotle, who in his physical
studies casually notes that substances might also be mixed, that is,
combined in such a manner that the combined substance vanish and a
new substance appears in their place. We may easily picture such a
mix through an example of adding sugar to water: the powdery sugar
vanishes, but also mere water, and in place of the two a sugary
liquid appears.
One might oppose my example with the
observation that the sugar and the water do not really vanish when
mixed, but sugar molecules merely disperse among the water molecules.
Yet, this observation itself is based on empirical studies and one
could not decide a priori whether
this particular case was a true mix or a mere assembling of lego
blocks. In other words, the example shows that Aristotelian mixes are
a conceivable possibility. Furthermore, it is also a possibility
which we could well comprehend and imagine: we could model any Aristotelian
mix through the picture of sugar combining with water.
Indeed, we need
even not think of mixing two substances of different sorts. It
suffices to picture a portion of water combining with another portion
of water. The result is not two portions of water, but one bigger
portion, or in other words, the original things have vanished in
combination and been replaced by a new thing. This conceptual
possibility is ingrained in the mass terms of some languages: things
like water do not appear to behave like the lego block model, thus,
we cannot e.g. speak meaningfully of several waters (we have to speak
of many portions of water etc.)
If the possibility
of an Aristotelian mix is admitted, Wolff's whole division of simple
and complex things becomes somewhat suspect. The simple things
should, on the one hand, be the ultimate constituents, which are
required for explaining the existence of the complex objects: they
should be the independent substances, while the complex substances
are contingently assembled from them.
Then again, simple
things should, on the other hand, be indivisible and they could not
have been generated through a combination of other things. Yet, if a
thing has been or at least could have been generated through an
Aristotelian mix, it would not be simple in the second sense, while
it well might be simple in the first sense, that is, an independent
substance. In other words, a substance might be generated from other
substances, but still not have any parts or constituents.
Wolff himself
actually considers the possibility that a simple thing could just
change into other simple things, somewhat like Aristotelian elements
– fire, air, water and earth – can change into one another. Yet,
he quickly disregards this possibility, because either it would be a
miracle where one substance is instantly destroyed and another takes
it place or then the apparently independent things are mere states of
one thing. Only with the latter option, Wolff adds, does the previous
state explain the latter state.
Wolff's denial of
Aristotelian change of elements is itself unfounded. Even less
convincing it is as a criticism of an Aristotelian mix. Although an
apparent change of one thing to another thing should be interpreted
as a mere change of state, an Aristotelian mix involves a combination
of several things into one unified thing, and it feels rather awkward
to call two separate things a mere state of their combination or vice
versa.
The flaw in Wolff's
division of things is important, because it suggests a similar
flaw in Kant's second antinomy. The antinomy should consist of two
equally convincing statements that could not hold at the same time:
”everything in the world consists of simple things” and ”there
is nothing simple in the world”. The two statements could well be
both true, if the simple things in the first statement meant final
constituents of assembled things, but the simple things in the second
statement meant indivisible substances. That is, the final
constituents might have no parts, but they could be so manipulated that
in place of a particular thing, many things would appear (this division is
essentially a reverse of the Aristotelian mix, and indeed, Aristotle
himself apparently thought divisions worked this way). We shall have
to return to the issue when we get to Kant's Critiques (it will
probably take twelve years).
Wolff's theory of
simple and complex things has other problems as well. For instance,
Wolff merely assumes that simple things cannot be observed. He does
not mean that we could not imagine what simple substances would be
like, and indeed, he admits that we perceive very small things as
having no discernible parts. Yet, Wolff notes that magnifying glasses
have proven that these apparently simple things are actually complex
– but this empirical evidence does still not prove the general
inobservability of simple things.
A more substantial
reason for the unobservability of simple things is Wolff's conviction
that simple things cannot be spatial, while all observable things
are. But why simple things couldn't be spatial? This is a question I
will consider next time, when I investigate Wolff's theories of space
and time.
Tilaa:
Blogitekstit (Atom)