The final part of Crusius’ natural theology is dedicated to the question of what God does, that is, what effects the divine activities produce. The obvious first answer for Crusius is that God has created the world, that is, the world that earlier was not has become existent. In the strictest sense, Crusius adds, creation refers to the generation of simple substances and their fundamental forces. In addition, God has also ordered these simple substances, but this is not something that only God could do.
God has not just created the world and everything in it, Crusius continues, but they also sustain all these things. Why couldn’t God just have created the things in such a manner that they would keep on existing without the help of God? Crusius’ answer is that this would have been impossible. Because the created things are contingent, their current existence is no reason why they would continue existing and thus they require the help of God for their continuous existence or otherwise they might as well just blink out of existence.
In addition to sustaining the existence of the things in the world, Crusius states, God also sustains the very order of the world. The threat here is not that the world would be completely wiped out of existence, but only that it would collapse into chaos. This threat is real, Crusius adds, because by themselves, material things would quickly move and change any given order.
Crusius adds that in some cases God sustains the actuality of certain things, but when free choices are involved, God can only sustain their possibility, while the actuality is then left for the decision of free beings. Thus, Crusius explains, God is not responsible for evil actions of free creatures, but merely sustains the possibility of such actions, which the action of a free person then makes real.
God does not just sustain the world, Crusius continues, but they direct the world in accordance with certain purposes. Original guidelines of this divine providence, he clarifies, are God’s fundamental desires, while what God attempts to achieve must have something to do with creatures capable of free actions, not with the mechanism of the material world. God is, as it were, building a kingdom, where the divine will morally obligates free creatures to do certain actions.
Crusius divided divine providence into such where God uses the course of nature to make something purposeful happen at appropriate time and such where God uses miracles or personally acts on the worldly things to make something happen. Since free spirits cannot be forced to do anything by natural causes, he points out, miracles must be especially used with them. Thus, particularly if there are plenty of evil free creatures, God has to do miracles, in order to assure the fulfilment of divine purposes. This still doesn’t mean that we should see miracles everywhere, since God can well use less miracles to produce more effects. In addition, Crusius notes, God need not make miracles obviously visible, unless the explicit purpose of the miracle is to be noted by human beings.
Näytetään tekstit, joissa on tunniste God. Näytä kaikki tekstit
Näytetään tekstit, joissa on tunniste God. Näytä kaikki tekstit
perjantai 13. tammikuuta 2023
tiistai 20. joulukuuta 2022
Christian August Crusius: Draft of necessary truths of reason, in so far as they are set opposite to contingent ones - What God is
It is one thing to say that something is, another to say what it is. Thus, it is no wonder that Crusius considers the question on the attributes of God, in addition to attempting to prove their existence. Yet, he also has to at first argue that we can speak reasonably about God. After all, as he himself admits, God should be so far above all finite things that we cannot ever really comprehend their essence.
One common way to describe God is through metaphors taken from human life, for instance, when we say that God hears or sees all things. Crusius accepts such anthropopathies, assuming that they are not understood in a too literal manner that would imply God's finity - this would be anthropomorphism.
Yet, Crusius is also keen to find out more literal attributes of God, in order to alleviate all accusations of humanising God. He notes that anthropathies can still provide an inkling of such literal attributes, if one can just remove the metaphorical element from them.
In fact, Crusius adds, all things can provide hints of what God is like. Firstly one can concentrate on how things are perfect and then assume that God is eminently more perfect. Secondly, one can pay attention to the fact that God must be able to create everything in the world. Beyond these two roads, Crusius suggests we have only a third route of describing God - negative one.
Well, Crusius does admit also a fourth, that of revelation. He especially refers to the notion of God as a Trinity, which he considers as the closest we come to knowing God's essence - or at least knowing an attribute that is not either an infinitised attribute of finite things or a relation. Indeed, Trinity - that of being a substance composed of three individuals - is something completely unique to God.
The other, non-revelatory attributes of God Crusius divides into non-active and active attributes, depending on whether the attributes involve any action or a capacity to an action. Foremost of the non-active attributes is infinity. This means, Crusius says, that God cannot have any imperfections. Furthermore, it implies that God has majestity, that is, that he is infinitely removed from all finite beings and inconceivable to them.
Although Trinity, Crusius insists, God is still simple. That is, the three persons of Godhead are in themselves incomplete, although they can e.g. have different actions. Furthermore, the simplicity of God implies that God is not material and that human souls are not a part of God.
Crusius is also convinced of the uniqueness of God, although he is not satisfied with many of the proofs suggested for this position. For instance, Crusius does not think that one could prove the uniqueness of God from the supposed impossibility of distinguishing infinite things, which would have all the same attributes - he points out that this distinction could still happen through relations or spatio-temporal characteristics. Neither does he approve the attempt to prove the uniqueness from the necessity of God, since there is nothing to show that there are only necessary things. Instead, Crusius favours a rather idiosyncratic proof: gods exist in space, and if there are several gods, they must exist in the same or different space, but in the latter case they would be finite, while the former is impossible.
In addition to these rather general attributes, Crusius’ non-active attributes for God contain also attributes related to what he calls the abstractions of existence or space and time. Here the case of time is perhaps easier to understand, since it just means that God is eternal or exists at all times (he does make the interesting suggestion that Trinity explains what God did before creation of the world: the three persons interacted with one another somehow).
The case of space is quite analogous, although Crusius’ result seems unusual: God is immense or they cannot be limited by anything. Crusius notes that this does not mean that God would consist of parts - the usual objection against God’s spatiality. Crusius explains himself by saying that the space of God is a mere abstraction and mere abstractions cannot be really broken into parts.
The active attributes of God refer, then, to those attributes of God that involve an action or a capacity for an action. On a general level, these attributes include that of God having an infinite force, that is, a force that can do everything that just happens to be possible. Some of the actions resulting from God using this force are a necessary part of their essence. Yet, all of them cannot be necessary, Crusius insists, and must be such that God can begin and stop doing them, because otherwise God would be less perfect than humans, who can do this.
Crusius also divides God’s actions into immanent actions that belong merely to the inner state of God’s essence and transient actions that either create a new substance or change the condition of a substance different from God. But can God create something different from itself, if God exists everywhere? Yes, Crusius asserts, as although two gods cannot occupy space, apparently God and a finite creature can.
Crusius notes that there are three kinds of actions: movement, understanding and will. Of these, God really cannot move, because as has been noted, God is everywhere. Then again, Crusius notes, God can definitely understand or think things - denying this would be implicit atheism, because otherwise God would be just a blind mechanism.
God’s understanding, Crusius says, should be infinite. This means, firstly, that God knows all there is and all there could be. Secondly, it means that God’s knowledge of actualities and possibilities must be perfect. For instance, God cannot take impossibilities as possibilities, God must know everything as distinctly as possible and therefore God definitely cannot know anything through sensations or deductions.
Crusius points out that God knows different things in a different manner. Some things, like possibilities and God’s own existence, God would know even if the world did not exist. God also has an encompassing vision of the world: its past, present and future. This vision includes, Crusius insists, also the actions of free creatures - we cannot understand how God can know them, but it is not contradictory. Between the two types of knowledge, Crusius states, God has also a third type: knowledge of what would happen, if a free person chose to do something.
In addition to understanding, Crusius assures us, God also has a will. Just like with divine actions, some of God’s volitions are necessary - these are God’s fundamental desires. With humans, Crusius recounts, fundamental desires include drive toward perfection, drive to share perfection to others, drive of conscience and bodily drive. The two latter cannot really be divine drives, but the two others can. God thus always desires to be perfect, and because they are, God is always infinitely happy or blessed.
God also desires perfection in things created, Crusius says, and this means that the world, if such exists, must form a moral system, where choices of free creatures can reflect divine perfection and all the other things can serve free creatures in fulfilling this purpose. Acting in accordance with divine perfection, Crusius suggests, means especially that free creatures must understand their dependence on God. God must thus give the free creatures laws that must be obeyed, and if the laws are not obeyed, God must punish the sinner. Crusius goes even further and insists that God can never really end the punishment, because this would mean that transgression would ultimately be forgotten and justice would not be served. He does concede that this might not mean that God would put sinners in an eternal torture, but only that a sinner is prevented from reaching the highest state of happiness possible.
Why did God then allow sinners to exist in the first place? Crusius’ first line of defence is that sinners were not created as sinners, but they freely chose to be such. Yet, this line of defence seems inadequate, since God still knew that the sinners would sin. Crusius’ second and rather cruel defence is that God had to be shown as a stern and righteous judge, since righteous punishment of sinners is a perfection.
In addition to punishing the sinners, God’s righteousness demands also rewarding the virtuous. Yet, God has also further reasons for this, since the second fundamental drive of God, Crusius says, is a desire to do good and show love to free creatures. Thus, God’s dice are loaded toward mercy and charity. Still, Crusius says, God won’t just hand out maximal amount of goodness to every creature, since this is ultimately impossible: there is no maximal goodness for finite creatures, since their goodness can always be increased.
In addition to these fundamental desires, God also has freedom, Crusius insists, that is, God can begin actions that otherwise wouldn’t have happened. This does not mean that even God’s free actions would be completely against their fundamental desires, in other words, that they wouldn’t satisfy God's desire for perfection and goodness. It is more that God has a complete freedom of not creating such a world at all, but has freely chosen to create it. Furthermore, Crusius emphasises, world could also have been otherwise, since God could have chosen many different means to fulfill the perfection of the world.
One common way to describe God is through metaphors taken from human life, for instance, when we say that God hears or sees all things. Crusius accepts such anthropopathies, assuming that they are not understood in a too literal manner that would imply God's finity - this would be anthropomorphism.
Yet, Crusius is also keen to find out more literal attributes of God, in order to alleviate all accusations of humanising God. He notes that anthropathies can still provide an inkling of such literal attributes, if one can just remove the metaphorical element from them.
In fact, Crusius adds, all things can provide hints of what God is like. Firstly one can concentrate on how things are perfect and then assume that God is eminently more perfect. Secondly, one can pay attention to the fact that God must be able to create everything in the world. Beyond these two roads, Crusius suggests we have only a third route of describing God - negative one.
Well, Crusius does admit also a fourth, that of revelation. He especially refers to the notion of God as a Trinity, which he considers as the closest we come to knowing God's essence - or at least knowing an attribute that is not either an infinitised attribute of finite things or a relation. Indeed, Trinity - that of being a substance composed of three individuals - is something completely unique to God.
The other, non-revelatory attributes of God Crusius divides into non-active and active attributes, depending on whether the attributes involve any action or a capacity to an action. Foremost of the non-active attributes is infinity. This means, Crusius says, that God cannot have any imperfections. Furthermore, it implies that God has majestity, that is, that he is infinitely removed from all finite beings and inconceivable to them.
Although Trinity, Crusius insists, God is still simple. That is, the three persons of Godhead are in themselves incomplete, although they can e.g. have different actions. Furthermore, the simplicity of God implies that God is not material and that human souls are not a part of God.
Crusius is also convinced of the uniqueness of God, although he is not satisfied with many of the proofs suggested for this position. For instance, Crusius does not think that one could prove the uniqueness of God from the supposed impossibility of distinguishing infinite things, which would have all the same attributes - he points out that this distinction could still happen through relations or spatio-temporal characteristics. Neither does he approve the attempt to prove the uniqueness from the necessity of God, since there is nothing to show that there are only necessary things. Instead, Crusius favours a rather idiosyncratic proof: gods exist in space, and if there are several gods, they must exist in the same or different space, but in the latter case they would be finite, while the former is impossible.
In addition to these rather general attributes, Crusius’ non-active attributes for God contain also attributes related to what he calls the abstractions of existence or space and time. Here the case of time is perhaps easier to understand, since it just means that God is eternal or exists at all times (he does make the interesting suggestion that Trinity explains what God did before creation of the world: the three persons interacted with one another somehow).
The case of space is quite analogous, although Crusius’ result seems unusual: God is immense or they cannot be limited by anything. Crusius notes that this does not mean that God would consist of parts - the usual objection against God’s spatiality. Crusius explains himself by saying that the space of God is a mere abstraction and mere abstractions cannot be really broken into parts.
The active attributes of God refer, then, to those attributes of God that involve an action or a capacity for an action. On a general level, these attributes include that of God having an infinite force, that is, a force that can do everything that just happens to be possible. Some of the actions resulting from God using this force are a necessary part of their essence. Yet, all of them cannot be necessary, Crusius insists, and must be such that God can begin and stop doing them, because otherwise God would be less perfect than humans, who can do this.
Crusius also divides God’s actions into immanent actions that belong merely to the inner state of God’s essence and transient actions that either create a new substance or change the condition of a substance different from God. But can God create something different from itself, if God exists everywhere? Yes, Crusius asserts, as although two gods cannot occupy space, apparently God and a finite creature can.
Crusius notes that there are three kinds of actions: movement, understanding and will. Of these, God really cannot move, because as has been noted, God is everywhere. Then again, Crusius notes, God can definitely understand or think things - denying this would be implicit atheism, because otherwise God would be just a blind mechanism.
God’s understanding, Crusius says, should be infinite. This means, firstly, that God knows all there is and all there could be. Secondly, it means that God’s knowledge of actualities and possibilities must be perfect. For instance, God cannot take impossibilities as possibilities, God must know everything as distinctly as possible and therefore God definitely cannot know anything through sensations or deductions.
Crusius points out that God knows different things in a different manner. Some things, like possibilities and God’s own existence, God would know even if the world did not exist. God also has an encompassing vision of the world: its past, present and future. This vision includes, Crusius insists, also the actions of free creatures - we cannot understand how God can know them, but it is not contradictory. Between the two types of knowledge, Crusius states, God has also a third type: knowledge of what would happen, if a free person chose to do something.
In addition to understanding, Crusius assures us, God also has a will. Just like with divine actions, some of God’s volitions are necessary - these are God’s fundamental desires. With humans, Crusius recounts, fundamental desires include drive toward perfection, drive to share perfection to others, drive of conscience and bodily drive. The two latter cannot really be divine drives, but the two others can. God thus always desires to be perfect, and because they are, God is always infinitely happy or blessed.
God also desires perfection in things created, Crusius says, and this means that the world, if such exists, must form a moral system, where choices of free creatures can reflect divine perfection and all the other things can serve free creatures in fulfilling this purpose. Acting in accordance with divine perfection, Crusius suggests, means especially that free creatures must understand their dependence on God. God must thus give the free creatures laws that must be obeyed, and if the laws are not obeyed, God must punish the sinner. Crusius goes even further and insists that God can never really end the punishment, because this would mean that transgression would ultimately be forgotten and justice would not be served. He does concede that this might not mean that God would put sinners in an eternal torture, but only that a sinner is prevented from reaching the highest state of happiness possible.
Why did God then allow sinners to exist in the first place? Crusius’ first line of defence is that sinners were not created as sinners, but they freely chose to be such. Yet, this line of defence seems inadequate, since God still knew that the sinners would sin. Crusius’ second and rather cruel defence is that God had to be shown as a stern and righteous judge, since righteous punishment of sinners is a perfection.
In addition to punishing the sinners, God’s righteousness demands also rewarding the virtuous. Yet, God has also further reasons for this, since the second fundamental drive of God, Crusius says, is a desire to do good and show love to free creatures. Thus, God’s dice are loaded toward mercy and charity. Still, Crusius says, God won’t just hand out maximal amount of goodness to every creature, since this is ultimately impossible: there is no maximal goodness for finite creatures, since their goodness can always be increased.
In addition to these fundamental desires, God also has freedom, Crusius insists, that is, God can begin actions that otherwise wouldn’t have happened. This does not mean that even God’s free actions would be completely against their fundamental desires, in other words, that they wouldn’t satisfy God's desire for perfection and goodness. It is more that God has a complete freedom of not creating such a world at all, but has freely chosen to create it. Furthermore, Crusius emphasises, world could also have been otherwise, since God could have chosen many different means to fulfill the perfection of the world.
sunnuntai 4. joulukuuta 2022
Christian August Crusius: Draft of necessary truths of reason, in so far as they are set opposite to contingent ones - Proving God’s existence
Diverging clearly from the Wolffian order of metaphysics, Crusius proceeds after ontology to natural theology. His justification is that while knowing the properties of things in the world requires knowing the properties of their creator, natural theology presupposes only a general concept of the world as a sum of all things, of which we we perceive a part and of which we ourselves are a part, and additionally some individual truths about souls.
Crusius’ first task in natural theology is to prove the existence of God, that is, an intelligent and necessary substance, which differs from the world and is the effective cause of the world. Crusius’ strategy is to throw everything at the wall and see what happens to stick, as he is willing to provide a whole bunch of different proofs, deeming the topic so important that it must be decided by any means necessary - the various proofs convince different people and corroborate one another. Crusius doesn’t even provide any other systematisation of this hodgepodge of proofs, except a classification based on the supposed strength of them.
The most certain proofs, Crusius says, are demonstrations that are ultimately based on the three principles of human cognition and of course principles derivable from them, such as the principle of sufficient reason and the principle of contingency (things that can be thought not to exist are contingent). Crusius presents altogether five of these demonstrations, all of which can be regarded as modifications of the cosmological proof in the Kantian classification. I will not go in detail to these proofs, but merely note their prominent features:
Crusius admits that it is possible that this order would have been fashioned from blind chaos by pure chance, or as Crusius suggests some atheists said, by a revolution in the structure of the world. Yet, Crusius instantly counters, such a revolution would have required an infinite number of coincidences, making the only option or the existence of God thus infinitely probable. Indeed, he argues, this proof shows clearest why God would have to be an intelligent substance and not mere force of nature.
The final or the lowest level of the proofs in Crusius scheme consists of such that result in finite probability. First two of those involve history. Crusius argues that the oldest history books (by which Crusius refers especially to the Bible and other myths) assume that the humankind has not existed forever and it is not probable that the first humans would have been created with natural means that do not work nowadays (e.g. humans being generated in the bowels of the earth). Furthermore, Crusius emphasises that during human history all nations have believed in some divine being or beings and asserts the improbability of a so widely spread deception.
Third of the merely probable proofs is based on the supposition that all humans have a conscience or a natural propensity to know what is right and what is wrong. Crusius argues that the universal existence of such a propensity cannot be a mere coincidence, generated by lucky circumstances, but must have been planned by the creator of humankind to help humans to decide what to do and what to avoid doing.
There is a conspicuous absence in Crusius’ battery of proofs - the ontological, or as it was then often called, the Cartesian proof. I noticed in an earlier post that Crusius would have accepted the proof in his ontology, but his theology clarifies that this is not the case - no proof of God’s existence can be based on a mere principle of contradiction, but some consideration of causality must happen. Crusius’ justification is evidently inherited from Hoffmann: although we cannot think the most perfect being without accepting its existence in our thoughts, this does not tell whether the most perfect being has existence outside our thoughts. If it would be a valid, Crusius adds, we might as well prove that the most perfect man and woman must exist, although the existence of men and women altogether is contingent.
What the Cartesian proof does say, according to Crusius, is that if God’s existence has been guaranteed otherwise, we can say this existence is necessary. This strategy is not that far from Wolff’s, who first proved God’s existence through a cosmological argument and then proceeded to show through an ontological argument why God must exist (because God is the most perfect being).
The main target of Crusius’ proofs are atheists. Crusius includes under atheists also people who doubt God’s existence. Such doubting atheists attack only the supposed weaknesses in the proofs of God’s existence, for instance, they might reject proof from the order in the world by pointing out imperfections in the world. Crusius’ answer to this particular objection is that what is imperfection from a limited point of view can actually contribute to the perfection of the whole world.
Another point the doubting atheists make, Crusius says, is that humans cannot really have a perfect conception of God and therefore it is as reasonable to deny as to accept God’s existence. Crusius insists that we do not need such a fully adequate concept of God to speak about their existence, but we have to just be able to distinguish God from other things. God is no empty word, Crusius assures, although we as finite things can know God mostly through negations or through God’s relations to other entities.
The more strict atheists, Crusius says, deny outright the existence of God. Some of these atheists are materialists, like ancient atomists, who consider even thinking and willing to be mere movement of matter and who do deny the existence of all simple intelligent substances. Other atheists Crusius groups under the title of universalists. Universalists he divides into those like Anaximander, who suppose that the final cause of the world can lie in the simple substances of the world, which may be intelligent, and those like Spinoza, who think of world as a unified simple substance, with things in it as mere properties of the substance. All of these forms of atheism, Crusius thinks, fall short in that they have to assume an infinite series of causes.
Crusius ends the discussion of the existence of God by noting that atheism is not the only erroneous view on theological matters. There are also deists, or as he also calls them, virtual atheists, who do not deny the existence of God, but only that of God being a moral lawgiver and judge. This is a topic he leaves for the next chapter on the attributes of God.
Crusius’ first task in natural theology is to prove the existence of God, that is, an intelligent and necessary substance, which differs from the world and is the effective cause of the world. Crusius’ strategy is to throw everything at the wall and see what happens to stick, as he is willing to provide a whole bunch of different proofs, deeming the topic so important that it must be decided by any means necessary - the various proofs convince different people and corroborate one another. Crusius doesn’t even provide any other systematisation of this hodgepodge of proofs, except a classification based on the supposed strength of them.
The most certain proofs, Crusius says, are demonstrations that are ultimately based on the three principles of human cognition and of course principles derivable from them, such as the principle of sufficient reason and the principle of contingency (things that can be thought not to exist are contingent). Crusius presents altogether five of these demonstrations, all of which can be regarded as modifications of the cosmological proof in the Kantian classification. I will not go in detail to these proofs, but merely note their prominent features:
- Crusius bases the existence of complex things on the existence of simple things, which they consist of. Then he uses the principle of contingency to show that simple things in the world are contingent and so require God for their existence.
- Crusius argues, as we have seen, that there are no infinite series of changes. This means, he insists, that the world must have been created by a substance that has existed eternally before creation.
- Crusius notes that all series of movements must be ultimately derived from an action of an infinite force.
- Crusius also uses the principle of contingency to directly conclude that the world is contingent.
- Crusius insists that plant and animal species must have originated from single individuals, which due to their well ordered nature must have been created by God.
Crusius admits that it is possible that this order would have been fashioned from blind chaos by pure chance, or as Crusius suggests some atheists said, by a revolution in the structure of the world. Yet, Crusius instantly counters, such a revolution would have required an infinite number of coincidences, making the only option or the existence of God thus infinitely probable. Indeed, he argues, this proof shows clearest why God would have to be an intelligent substance and not mere force of nature.
The final or the lowest level of the proofs in Crusius scheme consists of such that result in finite probability. First two of those involve history. Crusius argues that the oldest history books (by which Crusius refers especially to the Bible and other myths) assume that the humankind has not existed forever and it is not probable that the first humans would have been created with natural means that do not work nowadays (e.g. humans being generated in the bowels of the earth). Furthermore, Crusius emphasises that during human history all nations have believed in some divine being or beings and asserts the improbability of a so widely spread deception.
Third of the merely probable proofs is based on the supposition that all humans have a conscience or a natural propensity to know what is right and what is wrong. Crusius argues that the universal existence of such a propensity cannot be a mere coincidence, generated by lucky circumstances, but must have been planned by the creator of humankind to help humans to decide what to do and what to avoid doing.
There is a conspicuous absence in Crusius’ battery of proofs - the ontological, or as it was then often called, the Cartesian proof. I noticed in an earlier post that Crusius would have accepted the proof in his ontology, but his theology clarifies that this is not the case - no proof of God’s existence can be based on a mere principle of contradiction, but some consideration of causality must happen. Crusius’ justification is evidently inherited from Hoffmann: although we cannot think the most perfect being without accepting its existence in our thoughts, this does not tell whether the most perfect being has existence outside our thoughts. If it would be a valid, Crusius adds, we might as well prove that the most perfect man and woman must exist, although the existence of men and women altogether is contingent.
What the Cartesian proof does say, according to Crusius, is that if God’s existence has been guaranteed otherwise, we can say this existence is necessary. This strategy is not that far from Wolff’s, who first proved God’s existence through a cosmological argument and then proceeded to show through an ontological argument why God must exist (because God is the most perfect being).
The main target of Crusius’ proofs are atheists. Crusius includes under atheists also people who doubt God’s existence. Such doubting atheists attack only the supposed weaknesses in the proofs of God’s existence, for instance, they might reject proof from the order in the world by pointing out imperfections in the world. Crusius’ answer to this particular objection is that what is imperfection from a limited point of view can actually contribute to the perfection of the whole world.
Another point the doubting atheists make, Crusius says, is that humans cannot really have a perfect conception of God and therefore it is as reasonable to deny as to accept God’s existence. Crusius insists that we do not need such a fully adequate concept of God to speak about their existence, but we have to just be able to distinguish God from other things. God is no empty word, Crusius assures, although we as finite things can know God mostly through negations or through God’s relations to other entities.
The more strict atheists, Crusius says, deny outright the existence of God. Some of these atheists are materialists, like ancient atomists, who consider even thinking and willing to be mere movement of matter and who do deny the existence of all simple intelligent substances. Other atheists Crusius groups under the title of universalists. Universalists he divides into those like Anaximander, who suppose that the final cause of the world can lie in the simple substances of the world, which may be intelligent, and those like Spinoza, who think of world as a unified simple substance, with things in it as mere properties of the substance. All of these forms of atheism, Crusius thinks, fall short in that they have to assume an infinite series of causes.
Crusius ends the discussion of the existence of God by noting that atheism is not the only erroneous view on theological matters. There are also deists, or as he also calls them, virtual atheists, who do not deny the existence of God, but only that of God being a moral lawgiver and judge. This is a topic he leaves for the next chapter on the attributes of God.
sunnuntai 21. heinäkuuta 2019
Christian August Crusius: Instruction to live reasonably - Worshipping God
After talking about duties toward oneself, Crusius turns his interest to duties toward God. In some sense, he notes, we have been talking about them all the time, because all duties are based on God’s will and therefore duties toward God. Still, there are some duties that are specifically duties about God, which is their immediate object.
Now, one might wonder how God can be an object of a duty, since God is supposedly immutable and no one can actually do anything to him. Crusius clarifies that it is more a question of, firstly, our notion of God, and secondly, of our relationship to God. In other words, it is our immediate duty toward God to act in accordance with his perfection and our relationship to him.
It is thus our duty to obey God, Crusius says. In fact, he says, all duty is in a sense obeying God since God wants us to obey all duties. Crusius considers the question whether the duty to obey God would make God an awful tyrant. Crusius notes that this duty is not just arbitrary whimsy of a dictator, but flows from the very nature of divinity.
Two sides exist in human mind, Crusius continues, cognitive understanding and volitive will, and both have their own duties toward God. If we start from the side of the understanding, Crusius notes that we are obligated to know God, since it is noblest thing to know the ultimate source of everything. This does not mean that we should know God perfectly, since as we are imperfect entities, our knowledge is always limited. Still, we should try to know what God actually is and what kind of properties he has, what he wills and what he has achieved in the world (creating and sustaining the world, to start from the obvious). Furthermore, Crusius remarks, we should try to know other things as parts of a hierarchy, the pinnacle of which is God.
Yet, knowing God is not the only cognitive duty toward God that Crusius recognises. Indeed, he notes that in addition to knowledge we might have beliefs, not just in the broad sense of convictions, but in the sense of weaker convictions that might still be doubted. Now, Crusius says, we might have rational reasons to believe in this strict sense something, even if we couldn’t demonstrate its certainty. Particularly, he says, if disbelief would break an obligation toward God, we should choose belief, even if the truth of this belief could not be perfectly demonstrated. For instance, accepting general skepticism would imply that God has made us incapable of knowing anything, which Crusius considers a blasphemy. Even seemingly absurd statements about God (e.g. his trinitarian nature) should be believed, Crusius concludes, if there just is external evidence making it probable.
When it comes to will, Crusius suggests, we have a duty to love God, since God loves us also. This love of God implies that we try to live as virtuously as possible, since God wants us to be good. Other things implied by love of God, Crusius goes on, are that we should respect God, be thankful to him and humble ourselves before him.
All the duties mentioned thus far have been internal duties, that is, they concern our mental actions. We do have external duties toward God, Crusius insists. Firstly, all the so-called internal actions have some external signs, and we might say that showing the external signs of appropriate internal actions is an external duty. Then again, Crusius continues, we also have an external duty to e.g. pray to God, if we have difficulties in upholding our internal duties. Still, he concludes, there is no external duty toward God that would have no relation to internal duties.
Now, one might wonder how God can be an object of a duty, since God is supposedly immutable and no one can actually do anything to him. Crusius clarifies that it is more a question of, firstly, our notion of God, and secondly, of our relationship to God. In other words, it is our immediate duty toward God to act in accordance with his perfection and our relationship to him.
It is thus our duty to obey God, Crusius says. In fact, he says, all duty is in a sense obeying God since God wants us to obey all duties. Crusius considers the question whether the duty to obey God would make God an awful tyrant. Crusius notes that this duty is not just arbitrary whimsy of a dictator, but flows from the very nature of divinity.
Two sides exist in human mind, Crusius continues, cognitive understanding and volitive will, and both have their own duties toward God. If we start from the side of the understanding, Crusius notes that we are obligated to know God, since it is noblest thing to know the ultimate source of everything. This does not mean that we should know God perfectly, since as we are imperfect entities, our knowledge is always limited. Still, we should try to know what God actually is and what kind of properties he has, what he wills and what he has achieved in the world (creating and sustaining the world, to start from the obvious). Furthermore, Crusius remarks, we should try to know other things as parts of a hierarchy, the pinnacle of which is God.
Yet, knowing God is not the only cognitive duty toward God that Crusius recognises. Indeed, he notes that in addition to knowledge we might have beliefs, not just in the broad sense of convictions, but in the sense of weaker convictions that might still be doubted. Now, Crusius says, we might have rational reasons to believe in this strict sense something, even if we couldn’t demonstrate its certainty. Particularly, he says, if disbelief would break an obligation toward God, we should choose belief, even if the truth of this belief could not be perfectly demonstrated. For instance, accepting general skepticism would imply that God has made us incapable of knowing anything, which Crusius considers a blasphemy. Even seemingly absurd statements about God (e.g. his trinitarian nature) should be believed, Crusius concludes, if there just is external evidence making it probable.
When it comes to will, Crusius suggests, we have a duty to love God, since God loves us also. This love of God implies that we try to live as virtuously as possible, since God wants us to be good. Other things implied by love of God, Crusius goes on, are that we should respect God, be thankful to him and humble ourselves before him.
All the duties mentioned thus far have been internal duties, that is, they concern our mental actions. We do have external duties toward God, Crusius insists. Firstly, all the so-called internal actions have some external signs, and we might say that showing the external signs of appropriate internal actions is an external duty. Then again, Crusius continues, we also have an external duty to e.g. pray to God, if we have difficulties in upholding our internal duties. Still, he concludes, there is no external duty toward God that would have no relation to internal duties.
keskiviikko 29. elokuuta 2018
Joachim Darjes: Elements of metaphysics 2 – The city of God
While the metaphysical compendiums in Wolffian tradition have usually ended with a look on natural theology, Darjes has left cosmology as the final chapter of his metaphysics. This makes some sort of sense, since he has already emphasised that cosmology is no proper part of metaphysics, since it does not deal with characteristics of all things or of things from one of the highest genera of things – cosmology is about world, which is a certain complex of things, consisting of many kinds of things (in Darjesian philosophy, material bodies and immaterial souls and spirits).
Another oddity is Darjes' inclusion of certain notions from natural law to his discussion. He is particularly interested of the concept of right and possession. Right to something, for Darjes, means that a person has the ability to use that something without hurting other persons or their rights. This seemingly innocuous definition allows Darjes to conclude that in fact God is the primary owner of everything – God surely can control everything that exists, and he cannot really hurt rights of others, since he made all things in the first place.
Darjesian definition has also important consequences for the rights of finite entities. Firstly, he notes that finite entities can really have rights only for complex things, because they have no power to do anything to simple entities. Secondly, since all things already belong to God originally, finite entities can have right to anything, only if God has provided them the right to use things in some manner.
In addition to owning everything, God also governs world. This means that he sets the goals toward which this ”city of God” strives. The main purpose divinity has set for everything, according to Darjes, is the happiness and perfection of all rational beings. Thus, Darjes concludes, all rational beings should strive for their own happiness and perfection and help others to find these also – and definitely not hinder others in their search.
Darjes does not go into particularities of what actions are good for happiness and perfection, but merely notes what tools God uses for guiding rational entities toward their appointed goal. Firstly, God can directly reveal some guidelines. Secondly, God might appoint further rewards and punishments and even a kind of heaven and hell, to provide further incitement for good actions. Despite these rather naive Christian notions, Darjes also supposes that all rational entities will eventually be able to perfect themselves – the purpose of punishments is also just to help personal perfection.
Another oddity is Darjes' inclusion of certain notions from natural law to his discussion. He is particularly interested of the concept of right and possession. Right to something, for Darjes, means that a person has the ability to use that something without hurting other persons or their rights. This seemingly innocuous definition allows Darjes to conclude that in fact God is the primary owner of everything – God surely can control everything that exists, and he cannot really hurt rights of others, since he made all things in the first place.
Darjesian definition has also important consequences for the rights of finite entities. Firstly, he notes that finite entities can really have rights only for complex things, because they have no power to do anything to simple entities. Secondly, since all things already belong to God originally, finite entities can have right to anything, only if God has provided them the right to use things in some manner.
In addition to owning everything, God also governs world. This means that he sets the goals toward which this ”city of God” strives. The main purpose divinity has set for everything, according to Darjes, is the happiness and perfection of all rational beings. Thus, Darjes concludes, all rational beings should strive for their own happiness and perfection and help others to find these also – and definitely not hinder others in their search.
Darjes does not go into particularities of what actions are good for happiness and perfection, but merely notes what tools God uses for guiding rational entities toward their appointed goal. Firstly, God can directly reveal some guidelines. Secondly, God might appoint further rewards and punishments and even a kind of heaven and hell, to provide further incitement for good actions. Despite these rather naive Christian notions, Darjes also supposes that all rational entities will eventually be able to perfect themselves – the purpose of punishments is also just to help personal perfection.
We are now finally finished with Darjesian metaphysics. Next up on the list is a return to the work of Martin Knutzen.
sunnuntai 5. elokuuta 2018
Joachim Darjes: Elements of metaphysics 2 – Goal of creation
All Wolffian metaphysics thus far have concluded with natural theology – study of the infinite entity behind everything else. Although natural theology isn't the end of Darjesian metaphysics, he certainly wasn't able to ignore it completely. He starts by noting that an infinite entity is characterised by being perfect in all senses. Thus, infinite entity must be active and spontaneous. It must also not be dependent on anything, hence, it cannot be a material entity consisting of other entities. In other words, infinite entity must be a spirit, which acts perpetually. If there are infinite entities, Darjes finally notes, there can be only of them.
Now, Darjes notes that some philosophers have denied the existence of any infinite spirit. Such philosophers can be called atheists, since they deny the existence of God, which would be infinite spirit. But Darjes goes even further and insists that even skeptics that doubt the existence of an infinite spirit should be called atheists. Indeed, Darjes extends the notion of atheist even further, by defining God as a certain kind of infinite spirit – that is, God is also defined, according to him, by having freely created all the finite entities. Therefore, Aristotle, who thinks that the perfect self-thinking intellect has not created anything, and Stoics, who think that even divine Logos doesn't do anything freely, could be called atheists, Darjes concludes.
Darjes spends quite a lot of time on debunking the arguments of all these supposed atheists, but his main argument is undoubtedly his supposed proof of God's existence. While Christian Wolff based his assumption on the existence of God to a variant of cosmological argument – the existence of e.g. my own soul can be explained only through God – and used the so-called ontological argument merely as an explanation of God's existence (i.e. by noting that God in its perfection has all that it takes to exist) and while Baumgarten had exclusively relied on ontological argument (that is, by arguing that a combination of all perfections must also contain perfection of existence), Darjes appears to just try to throw various arguments and see what sticks. He begins by noting that a notion of infinite spirit must be possible – indeed, spirits are possible, and there seems to be no problem in supposing a spirit that is more perfect than anything else, he insists. Then, Darjes continues, infinite spirit must exist, because it is such a thing that exists, if it just is possible. As if not completely convinced of this ontological proof, Darjes defends the existence of God with two other proofs – firstly, he uses the cosmological argument that all finite entities must be dependent on God, and secondly, a somewhat weaker proof that God's existence is probable, because otherwise we would have to make too many assumptions to explain everything in the world.
A topic that Darjes seems to regard as wanting a more thorough examination is the characterisation of God. A general foundation of the examination is that as a perfect entity God must have also perfect attributes. Indeed, these attributes are unique to God, Darjes says, and one cannot then make a true distinction between God's essence and his attributes, because there isn't any entity that would have similar attributes and still not be God.
Darjes notes that some attributes of God, such as his infinity, spirituality, immutability, necessity and uniqueness, do not concern anything that God does, while others or the so-called operational attributes do. A good example of the latter is the cognition of God, which should be the best kind of cognition possible – that is, Darjes says, God should be omnipotent. This omnipotent cognition of God is for Darjes threefold. Firstly, God knows through his very constituting force all the things that could be – this is natural cognition of God. Secondly, God also knows freely all the things happening through his spontaneous actions. Finally, Darjes notes, God must have cognition mediating between the other two kinds of cognition, that is, cognition of causal chains that lead to actualisation of different possibilities.
A counterpart to God's cognition is his volition, which Darjes classifies into two kinds corresponding with two kinds of God's cognition. Firstly, God wills through his very nature that all things must cohere with all the attributes of God. Of course, Darjes notes, all things simply must cohere with the perfection of divinity. In other words, God wills that some things, which necessarily are in a certain manner, must be as they are. Secondly, God's volitions are not restricted to necessities, but God also wills things that might not be as they are, such as the existence of some non-divine entities. Whatever the kind of volition, Darjes notes, the object of this volition must be optimally good. More particularly, God wills that there are finite, but free entities, that they will always have means for perfecting themselves through their free actions and that they should not squander their freedom. Furthermore, Darjes remarks, God never wills anything evil, but at most permits evil, that is, lets something bad happen, if it is necessary for the existence of something even more good. God doesn't even punish people, Darjes says, if this punishment does not contribute to the development of the punished persons.
Merely willing, God would just decree things, but in addition, he also executes his decrees, Darjes notes. In particular, this means that God has caused the existence of finite entities, that is, has created them. Darjes notes that it is unsure whether this act of creation happened at some particular point or whether it has been going on through eternity. In any case, Darjes continues, God does not just create finite things, but also continues to sustain them with the same act, by which he created them in he first place. God could, undoubtedly, just annihilate all finite entities, but he doesn't have any reason to do that.
Now, Darjes notes that some philosophers have denied the existence of any infinite spirit. Such philosophers can be called atheists, since they deny the existence of God, which would be infinite spirit. But Darjes goes even further and insists that even skeptics that doubt the existence of an infinite spirit should be called atheists. Indeed, Darjes extends the notion of atheist even further, by defining God as a certain kind of infinite spirit – that is, God is also defined, according to him, by having freely created all the finite entities. Therefore, Aristotle, who thinks that the perfect self-thinking intellect has not created anything, and Stoics, who think that even divine Logos doesn't do anything freely, could be called atheists, Darjes concludes.
Darjes spends quite a lot of time on debunking the arguments of all these supposed atheists, but his main argument is undoubtedly his supposed proof of God's existence. While Christian Wolff based his assumption on the existence of God to a variant of cosmological argument – the existence of e.g. my own soul can be explained only through God – and used the so-called ontological argument merely as an explanation of God's existence (i.e. by noting that God in its perfection has all that it takes to exist) and while Baumgarten had exclusively relied on ontological argument (that is, by arguing that a combination of all perfections must also contain perfection of existence), Darjes appears to just try to throw various arguments and see what sticks. He begins by noting that a notion of infinite spirit must be possible – indeed, spirits are possible, and there seems to be no problem in supposing a spirit that is more perfect than anything else, he insists. Then, Darjes continues, infinite spirit must exist, because it is such a thing that exists, if it just is possible. As if not completely convinced of this ontological proof, Darjes defends the existence of God with two other proofs – firstly, he uses the cosmological argument that all finite entities must be dependent on God, and secondly, a somewhat weaker proof that God's existence is probable, because otherwise we would have to make too many assumptions to explain everything in the world.
A topic that Darjes seems to regard as wanting a more thorough examination is the characterisation of God. A general foundation of the examination is that as a perfect entity God must have also perfect attributes. Indeed, these attributes are unique to God, Darjes says, and one cannot then make a true distinction between God's essence and his attributes, because there isn't any entity that would have similar attributes and still not be God.
Darjes notes that some attributes of God, such as his infinity, spirituality, immutability, necessity and uniqueness, do not concern anything that God does, while others or the so-called operational attributes do. A good example of the latter is the cognition of God, which should be the best kind of cognition possible – that is, Darjes says, God should be omnipotent. This omnipotent cognition of God is for Darjes threefold. Firstly, God knows through his very constituting force all the things that could be – this is natural cognition of God. Secondly, God also knows freely all the things happening through his spontaneous actions. Finally, Darjes notes, God must have cognition mediating between the other two kinds of cognition, that is, cognition of causal chains that lead to actualisation of different possibilities.
A counterpart to God's cognition is his volition, which Darjes classifies into two kinds corresponding with two kinds of God's cognition. Firstly, God wills through his very nature that all things must cohere with all the attributes of God. Of course, Darjes notes, all things simply must cohere with the perfection of divinity. In other words, God wills that some things, which necessarily are in a certain manner, must be as they are. Secondly, God's volitions are not restricted to necessities, but God also wills things that might not be as they are, such as the existence of some non-divine entities. Whatever the kind of volition, Darjes notes, the object of this volition must be optimally good. More particularly, God wills that there are finite, but free entities, that they will always have means for perfecting themselves through their free actions and that they should not squander their freedom. Furthermore, Darjes remarks, God never wills anything evil, but at most permits evil, that is, lets something bad happen, if it is necessary for the existence of something even more good. God doesn't even punish people, Darjes says, if this punishment does not contribute to the development of the punished persons.
Merely willing, God would just decree things, but in addition, he also executes his decrees, Darjes notes. In particular, this means that God has caused the existence of finite entities, that is, has created them. Darjes notes that it is unsure whether this act of creation happened at some particular point or whether it has been going on through eternity. In any case, Darjes continues, God does not just create finite things, but also continues to sustain them with the same act, by which he created them in he first place. God could, undoubtedly, just annihilate all finite entities, but he doesn't have any reason to do that.
maanantai 15. helmikuuta 2016
Baumgarten: Metaphysics – Divine deeds
Like majority of the
German philosophers at the time, Baumgarten was quick to distance his
ideas from Spinozism. Thus, he insists that God is not just a passive
source of emanation, but an active creator. Of course, God has not
created everything, Baumgarten says. Essences of all things are
necessary and thus in need of no creation. Since essences of things
contain their necessary limitations, Baumgarten can also say that God
is not the cause of these limitations – whatever evil there is in
the world, is then ultimately no fault of God.
What God has done
then is that he has given existence to some of the essences and their
complex or the world. With the world, he created all its parts, down
to the simple substances or monads. Because God knows best, this
world must be the best possible, even though it necessarily has some
evil due to the limitations of the substances. Quite traditionally,
Baumgarten suggests that the end of the creation is to reflect the
glory of divinity, especially in the eyes of all substances with
intellect to comprehend the perfection of the world and its creator.
Baumgarten also
states, again quite traditionally, that God has not just created the
world, but also sustains its continued existence. This means
especially that God makes sure that world follows certain stable
physical laws. Such stable laws might allow some evil to happen – a
human being might be killed, because a bullet follows a certain
trajectory. Still, this is not something that God would have
positively wanted to happen, but just something he has allowed as a
consequence of the working of natural laws.
God can have more
specific influence in world's events. Such special influence cannot
then have any bad effects, since it is something God has positively
willed to happen. Indeed, Baumgarten assures us, the aim of these
divine interventions is often to help the frail worldly creatures and
prevent them from succumbing to their limitations. One particular
type of such interventions is revelation, which in strict sense means
for Baumgarten God speaking supernaturally to finite beings. The
content of such revelation is usually something that humans could not
have found out by themselves, but it can never contradict what
philosophy has to say about world and God.
With such
traditionally religious notions ends Baumgarten's Metaphysics. Next
time, I shall take a look at how to combine necessity with freedom.
sunnuntai 7. helmikuuta 2016
Baumgarten: Metaphysics – Pulling God out of the hat
It is especially in
his rational theology where Baumgarten diverges most from standards
set by Wolff. As we should know by now, for Wolff, it was the
cosmological argument that ruled the field of theology. With
Baumgarten, we find no traces of this argument. Instead, Baumgarten
starts straightaway with the ontological argument, which with Wolff
clearly played a second fiddle.
The two gentlemen
don't just have different taste in arguments, but their very
arguments are different. Indeed, when with Wolff, ontological
argument was essentially dependent on cosmological argument, with
Baumgarten, the ontological argument obviously has to work on its
own.
There's already a
clear difference in the manner, in which Wolff and Baumgarten try to
prove the possibility of God. With Wolff, the proof was based on the
fact that he defined God as a sum of known possibilities that are also
known to be possible in combination – it requires just quick
analysis to see that this proof must work. Baumgarten, on the
contrary, bases his proof on more spurious ideas. He defines God as a
sum of positive characteristics, which have no negations or
limitations in them. He then suggests that contradiction could only
occur, if such a combination of characteristics would have some
negations in them. This leap of thought seems to require a more
careful justification – after all, one might think that
characteristics might restrict one another without being literal
negations of one another. Yet, it seems that with Baumgarten,
development of a thing in one dimension is completely indifferent to
its development in another dimension – basic characteristics are
independent of one another.
Now, with Wolff, it
is then all about knowing whether his combination of perfect possible
characteristics is just a contingent entity or also necessary – in
the former case, we can say nothing about its existence, in the latter
case, we can conclude infallibly that it does exist. The only manner
in which Wolff could decide this was to show that necessary things
existed – this is where the cosmological argument came in.
Baumgarten, on the
other hand, simply assumes that existence is one of the independent
dimensions, of which the sum of all positive characteristics
consists of. As one knows well, Kant was very much against this idea
and denied that being or existence would be even a characteristic in
the same sense as other characteristics of things. Wolff did not go
as far, because he noted that Baumgartenian line of thought could not
lead very far – even if you added existence as a characteristic of
some possible entity, it would still be just possible existence (this
is why he had to prove a stronger notion that he could add necessity
to the required possible combination of perfect characteristics).
With Baumgarten, actual existence is something you can just add to a
possible thing and make it exist – indeed, existence is defined by him as a completeness in
the combination of all characteristics of a thing.
Baumgarten then
thinks that he has shown the necessity of God's existence – God
comes out, when you start to add all sorts of perfections and finally
existence. God cannot then fail to exist, because that would mean
contradiction. Baumgarten's final account of all the properties of
God is rather traditional (he is all-knowing, all-powerful and
perfectly good), but one should not even expect originality in such
carefully observed part of education.
Next time, I shall
wrap up Baumgarten's natural theology, and with it, all of
Baumgarten's metaphysics.
maanantai 6. huhtikuuta 2015
Christian Wolff: Natural theology, posterior part – The enemies of faith
Included with the
second book of Natural theology is also Wolff's first complete take
on worldviews that rivaled Christianity – one might
suppose that it was especially atheism controversy that generated his
interest in the topic. It is no wonder that Wolff rejects all these
theories, but what is interesting is how he groups these various
viewpoints into distinct sets.
The most important
of the wrong theories is obviously atheism, which Wolff thinks is so
important that it deserves a chapter of its own. We all know atheists
are of the opinion that God does not exist. What is more, a
consistent atheist must even deny the possibility of God, because by
Wolff's a priori proof, God would exist, if he just were possible.
Because God does not exist, there is no final explanation of the
world, but instead, the world must be an independent entity requiring
no explanation – a strange conclusion in Wolffian eyes, because
nothing extended could be really independent for Wolff. The worldly
events must either go on forever or form a loop in which things
repeat one another. In any case, they must follow an iron necessity,
since nothing outside the universe could come and change anything.
This doesn't mean that there would be no freedom, since human souls
might still have the freedom to do things – this freedom just
probably would have no consequences on the level of material world.
Still, it means that morality is difficult to combine with atheism,
because the necessity of the world makes it impossible to apply
values like good or bad to it.
After atheism, Wolff
groups together fatalism, deism and naturalism, probably because his
pietist opponents had often grouped these three together. Fatalism,
or the idea that everything in the world happens necessarily, is
evidently the one Wolff likes least. Wolff clearly states that
atheists must inevitably be fatalists, at least if they want to
accept the laws of physics. Still, all fatalists need not be
atheists, but they may well be deists, that is, they may believe that
God has just created the world, but does not afterwards interfere with
it in any manner. Wolff also points out that deist, like atheist,
cannot use the idea of divine providence as a way to booster people's
behaviour, yet, deist can be more consistent with morality, because he
can accept that God might have chosen another world, which might have
been better or worse.
Still, it is the
third idea or naturalism that is the most interesting of the three
theories. By naturalism Wolff does not mean belief in natural
sciences, but the idea of natural theology as the only true source
of religion. Wolff might have sympathised with the view, but he
clearly wanted to show also that natural theology and revealed
religion need not be rivals, but could in many cases meet one another.
It is not so strange
to see materialism and idealism in the same chapter, but
anthropomorphism seems a stranger bedfellow. Yet, Wolff obviously has
a point – if God is thought to be shaped like a human, he is obviously
material or at least has a material constituent. This also shows that
materialist need not necessarily be atheist, since she can just
assume that God is some material things (perhaps even the world
itself).
Wolff criticizes
both anthropomorphists and materialists, because they make God into
something very ungodlike – a material object that could be cut to
pieces. Interestingly Wolff is less critical of idealism and even
says that idealist need not deny physics, because she can just think
it concerns an apparent world. Still, Wolff finally denies idealism,
because it takes away from the glory of God, who then wouldn't have
created an independent world.
The final chapter of
the book gathers together various philosophical theories, but also
paganism or belief in the existence of several gods, which is perhaps
highlihted, because it shares similarities with Manicheanism: both
theories suggest that there are several principles guiding world and
thus they essentially lower the status of God. The final two systems,
Spinozism and Epicureanism, are quickly dealt with. Spinoza has the disadvantage, because it clearly confuses the notion of
independency and substance – God is the only independent thing and
others are God's creations, but these creations surely are not parts
of God. Epicureanism, on the other hand, falls from traditional
reasons – emphasising mere sensual pleasure destroys values in
themselves.
Finally a last page
on Wolff's natural theology. Next time I'll turn to a new philosopher.
sunnuntai 29. maaliskuuta 2015
Christian Wolff: Natural theology, prior part – God and the world
In the beginning,
God might have created heaven and earth, but it is hard to explain
what God did in this supposed creation. First there was no world and
then there was one, but because we cannot do such things, these words
do not convey any clear meaning. It appears that in case of creation,
whether there was such thing or not, we are always incapable of truly
understanding what it is all about.
Christian Wolff
tries to shed some light on the topic. World is dependent on its
elements, so in creating the world, God must have used the elements.
Because elements, on the other hand, are dependent on the very world
they should constitute, God cannot have used elements as a
construction matter, but he must have begun his labourious efforts by
creating the elements out of nothing. At the same time as he created
elements, God ordered them to various structures constituting the
world itself. On top of all this, he also created finite souls to
think this world.
Now, Wolff believed
that space and time are relational, that is, that there would be no
space and time without any spatial and temporal things. Thus, space
and time did not exist before creation, but both began to exist in
the creation.
Since Wolffian God
is supposed to exist beyond time, it seems hard to decide whether the
world is supposed to be finite in its history or whether God created
it as having existed for an infinity. Here, on the other hand, Wolff
is willing to accept that there is a first state of the world.
Because this beginning is not explained by anything in the world, it
must be miraculous, Wolff concludes. This appears to be actually the
first time when Wolff explicitly admits time has a first moment –
it might be that he is trying to prove his non-Spinozism by this
move.
God is then capable
of doing the miracle of bringing truly new things into existence,
while no other thing can do this, but is only restricted to modifying
what is already given. Indeed, nothing else would even exist without
God, because he is also preserving world. Of course, Wolff notes,
since God is atemporal, his act of preservation is the same as his
act of creation.
Wolff's God is still
not just a creator and upholder of the world, but just like in
Christian tradition usually, he has designed the world down to its
last details. Indeed, God is a moral being who has wisely set up the
machinery of the universe in such a manner that it serves some higher
end, which obviously must be good – God is providential, which can
be seen in the fact that all things in the world are of use to one
another.
Especially in case
of rational beings, like humans, God has set up some goals, which
they should strive to obtain – God gives human an opportunity to
perfect some part of the world. Of course, God doesn't force anyone
to follows his councils, but merely creates an obligation that we
should follow them. It is then up to an individual whether she wants
to follow God, but in the end it would be in her best interests to
follow them, since God's rules should be of benefit to anyone.
All in all, Wolff
appears to know quite a lot of what God is like, what he has done,
and what he wants of us. On a closer look, Wolff admits that we know
not very much about this God. We know that God is the final ground of
everything, but this is about as much as we can say. Many of the
supposed divine attributes are mere negations – final ground of
world is not material, but he isn't also any human soul. Then again,
the supposed positive attributes of God are only eminent, that is,
they are somehow similar as some of our own attributes, but in
reality quite incomprehensible, because we do not know e.g. what an
infinite understanding would be like. When people of Kantian leanings
thus accuse Wolff of a philosophical arrogance and of an attempt to base
substantial knowledge of God on mere concepts, these accusations do
not hit the mark – our knowledge of what God is, is rather meager.
So much for the
first past of Wolff's theology, onward to second!
keskiviikko 25. maaliskuuta 2015
Christian Wolff: Natural theology, prior part – Good and powerful
Wolffian God is not
satisfied with mere contemplation of possibilities, but decides to
actualise one of the possible worlds. In order to do this, he needs
to have the capacity to actualise anyone of them. Indeed, God could
make anything happen that is possible and only impossibilities are
limits to his capacities – in effect, God is omnipotent, Wolff
says.
What God requires
for this use of his capacity is mere act of will. This is of course
completely different from what human beings do – in us, decision
and actualisation of a plan are two completely distinct events. In
fact, there is an even further difference, Wolff says. Human beings
usually start by contemplating all the possibilities and only after
careful consideration make their choice. With God, these two events
are connected in one act – God chooses even in contemplating
possibilities.
Now, when God chose
to actualise this world, he knew exactly what would happen in this
world, because he knows everything that would happen in any possible
world. This appears to lead to the famous problem of divine
prescience – how could our choices be completely free, if God
already knows what we are going to choose beforehand. The answer to
this problem is also quite traditional – knowing something does not
cause it, thus, even if God knows what Obama will do tomorrow, he did
not choose it for Obama's sake. Of course, this line of reasoning has
the striking weakness that God does choose the world that is to be
actualised and seems so responsible of everything that happens in the
world.
What is more
important is that God must have had some reason for picking this
particular world – as we know already, Wolff thinks it is because
the actual world is the most perfect of all worlds. The Leibnizian
story of a necessary evil which all worlds must have and which God
doesn't cause, but only allows should be familiar by now. Wolff also
emphasises God's wisdom and goodness. God is wise or he knows the best
means for actualising his ends, thus, the world and its laws are the
most efficient there can be and allow, for instance, human beings to
actualise their ends. Indeed, God has given humans liberty, because
he is good and hopes they will of their own choice make good
decisions – and even if they don't and end up doing evil things, in
the end, even this serves the final good.
God's wisdom is then
for the most part incomprehensible to human beings – we simply
cannot see all the strings that should turn evil actions into good
effects. Yet, God can reveal us information that goes over what we
can directly know through experience – Wolff's take on the idea of
divine revelation. This is also a good place to stop, because in next
post I will finally think of the ways God effects other things, that
is, nature and spirits.
sunnuntai 22. maaliskuuta 2015
Christian Wolff: Natural theology, prior part (1736)
Wolff's Latin series
of metaphysical works is finished by his Theologia naturalis.
While from the modern perspective this must be the least interesting
part of Wolff's system, it is, on the contrary, largest of all the
Latin metaphysical works, and indeed, was published in two volumes.
The first volume begins with
a brief explanation of what natural theology is all about, but
is especially characterised by an a posteriori method – that is,
Wolff attempts to use experience to determine the existence and
properties of God. The second
volume should then obviously use an a priori method – a novelty in
Wolffian system, and we shall see how it fits in with the more
established part of his theology.
Wolff's
primary route for God's existence has always been through what Kant
would later call a cosmologial proof.
Wolff begins by admitting the existence of reader's own soul – if
nothing else exists then I at least exist. Then Wolff notes that
there must be a complete grounding of the existence of this soul.
Complete ground or reason can then be only something which does not
require any further
explanation or anything
external for its own existence. It is clear this proof has a number
of weak points. What is this grounding supposed to mean? If it is
just a nickname for a mental demand of human consciousness that all
things must be fully grounded, then we clearly need not take it
seriously as an ontological principle – even if I'd have to insist
on God's existence, this would not necessitate God's actual
existence. Then again, it appears unreasonable to suppose that the
complete ground in an
ontological sense
couldn't be an infinite
series of past events,
especially if one believed that such a series would be necessary.
Whatever
the case, the rest of the book sets out to discover further
characteristics of this final explanation of everything. The
most straightforward feature is that while God, like all entities,
must have some force, it must be a force that requires nothing
external for activating it. In effect, if there is no inherent
contradiction in the structure of God, it will, as it were, actualise
itself, no matter what – we shall return to this idea, when we are
dealing with the second book on natural theology. Figuratively one
can say that God existed before anything else and God will exist
after anything else.
God's
necessity and self-sufficiency reveal at least what God cannot be.
God cannot have been generated in a literal sense of the term and he
definitely cannot be destroyed – thus, he cannot be material. Then
again, because human souls are essentially dependent on the world
they represent, God cannot be a human soul. Still, God has chosen to
create a particular world and so must have some mental activities or
be spirit. In fact, by thinking what sort of spiritual activities are
required in an act of creation, one can try to determine what God is
like.
Now,
in order that God can choose a world to create, he must have
first checked out all the possibilities from which to choose the
world to be created – in effect, God must have considered all the
possible worlds. This means
that God must have some cognitive activities, yet, they are of quite
different type than human cognition. For starters, God does not have
any passive faculties, because he is constantly acting or cognising
things. Furthermore, God does not need to move from one aspect of a
world to another, but he comprehends immediately everything that
would happen in one possible world. Because possible worlds contain
all that there might be, God is definitely omniscient.
If
God then knows all things perfectly well, can he also know what we
know, as we know it? Well, God cannot fail to have a perfect knowledge, thus, he
cannot force himself into a mode in which he would have only human
type of knowledge of world and cannot therefore have any firsthand experience on the condition of human consciousness. Still, God can know that some other
person has a more imperfect view of the world.
Because
God can at once see all the past, present and future events, he has
complete historical knowledge of all individual things. This does not
mean that God could not have universal or philosophical knowledge
also. Indeed, God can intuitively know whether certain feature of
things is universally connected to another feature, so making him the
greatest scientist of all times. Of
course, even in universal knowledge God is not restricted to any use
of symbols, although he does see that humans usually require such
aids for universal knowledge.
Before moving onto
more active side of divine attributes, it is good to note in passing
that Wolff also used considerable number of pages for determining
whether Bible got it right – that is, whether e.g. Bible is
correct, if it says that God sees something, or whether it must be
using symbolic language. It is a bold move, especially considering
accusations of atheism against Wolff and the recent schism with the Wertheimer Bible, that Wolff even considers such
questions, even if these questions feel rather dated nowadays. Next time more
about the divine will.
tiistai 12. maaliskuuta 2013
Christian Wolff: Remarks on Reasonable thoughts on God, the world and the human soul, also on all things in general - Fragments of cosmology, rational psychology and natural theology
It has become evident that Wolff clearly
wants to distance himself from the image of a radical atheist and Spinozist.
This is even more evident, if we take into consideration his comments
on cosmology, which he straightforwardly defines as a discipline required
especially for the proof of God's existence. Indeed, it is the
contingency of the world and its dependence on God that Wolff
especially wants to emphasize in his comments – thus, he once again
uses considerable efforts to state the difference between absolute
and hypothetical necessity, which his opponents had muddled.
Wolff also clarifies the notion that
things are infinitely dependent on other things, which I also noted
to be somewhat confusing statement and which the pietists read as a
commitment to the eternity of the world. Wolff notes that he is
merely stating what the worldly things would have to be like, if only natural explanations or causation according to natural laws would be
allowed. In other words, there couldn't have been a natural beginning
of the world, because every natural law requires a previous state
from which the current state arose.
Such an impossibility does not of
course rule out a supernatural beginning or a beginning that did not
happen according to natural laws. Indeed, Wolff is convinced that the
principle of sufficient ground must then lead us to accept such a
supernatural beginning – infinite series of causes just isn't a
possibility. Wolff is here underlining the contingency of natural
laws: they are necessary only within the world, but not from a more
extensive perspective.
Furthermore, Wolff even makes it clear
that in a sense natural laws are not necessary even within the world,
that is, if God is taken into account. Wolff states that God need not
follow laws of nature, but if he so desires, he can make worldly
things behave in a manner they usually wouldn't. Of course, Wolff is
quick to point out that God doesn't do such miracles, unless there is a good
reason, but it is evident that he wants to make God's freedom stand
more out.
Interestingly, Wolff appears to take
the principle of the identity of indiscernibles as a mere natural
law. Indeed, he does consider it a real possibility that God could
have created two completely equal things, although he just has had no
reason to do it. We can see Wolff distancing himself here from
Leibniz, who apparently suggested that the identity of indiscernibles
might somehow be based on the principle of sufficient reason.
Even clearer is Wolff's struggle
against becoming identified a a mere Leibnizian in his behaviour
towards monadology. Wolff does want to present the theory of monads
in as plausible manner as possible, but he emphasizes forcefully
that he himself does not believe in it. Main reasons for his
disbelief are physical. Wolff is unconvinced that all the richness of
phenomena could be reduced to elements that all share the same force
of representation. True, one could on basis of this power understand
why elements or monads can form larger totalities, such a material
objects, but the further characteristic of material objects that resist the intrusion of other material objects into the same place is
something Wolff cannot understand as derived from force of
representation.
Still further clue of Wolff's growing
disenchanment of Leibniz is provided by Wolff's clarification of the
status of pre-established harmony as a mere hypothesis, but this is
something we have already dealt with. In addition, Wolff seems keen
to downplay the importance of whole rational psychology: if one just
knows e.g. that movements of soul and body somehow correspond with
one another, nothing more is required, if one does not have a
scientific bent for discovering grounds for everything.
The urge to distinguish himself from
Leibnizian thought is probably a symptom of Wolff's need to answer
the accusations of atheism and fatalism, which becomes even more
evident in the rest of Wolff's book. Thus, Wolff spends considerable
number of pages in explaining that while one can derive all
properties of souls from its representative capacities and all
properties of God from his capacity to view all possible worlds at
once, this does not mean that the nature of soul and God would be
mere theoretical or passive regard of actual and possible worlds, but
that both soul and God are active. And just like Wolff decided to
defend the freedom of the soul, equally certain is his tendency to
defend the divine liberty – even if the act of creating this world is
the most reasonable and God as eminently good and wise will then
inevitably choose to create it, this still doesn't mean that God
couldn't have chosen completely different world to create.
Thus end Wolff's remarks on his
metaphysics, which set his scheduled publication back a year – it
was only the next year that Wolff could finally publish his account
of biology, to which I shall turn next time.
Tunnisteet:
best of all possible worlds,
Christian Wolff,
cosmology,
God,
metaphysics,
monads,
natural theology,
psychology,
rational psychology,
soul,
world
perjantai 4. tammikuuta 2013
Christian Wolff: Of different interconnections between things, wisdom and fatalistic necessity, system of pre-established harmony and Spinozan hypothesis splendidly commented, while at the same time weighing justifications for demonstrating existence of genuine God and illustrating many chapters of rational theology (1724)
We have just seen Lange's thorough
criticism of Wolffian philosophy leading to the surprising conclusion
that Wolff was no better than a common atheist like Spinoza was
thought to be. By coincidence, Wolff had the very same year written a
treatise – De differentia nexus rerum sapientis, nec non
systematis harmoniae praestabilitae et hypothesium Spinosae luculenta
commentatio, in qua simul genuina Dei existantiam demonstrandi ratio
expenditur et multa religionis naturalis capita illustrantur
– where he explicitly tried to show how the Leibnizian tradition
differed from Spinozism.
As the title so
clearly says, Wolff tried to establish two points of difference: one
concerned the supposed necessity of the world, while the issue of
second was the interaction of souls and bodies. Of these two points,
the second is easier to decide. True, it appears that Wolff and
Spinoza have identical views of the topic: both deny any true
interaction of souls and bodies and maintain that the series of
bodily changes and the series of mental states should somehow reflect
one another. Yet, there is a crucial difference. Leibniz and Wolff
envisioned the body and the soul as two different substances, while
Spinoza thought them to be mere aspects of one human being. With
Spinoza then, as Wolff's student Bilfinger had already pointed out,
bodies and souls were necessarily intertwined. Wolff and Leibniz, on
the contrary, accept that the union of the two substances is
contingent and therefore separable. This is important especially as a
justification of the Christian notion of life after death – soul or
consciousness might exist also without any body to sustain it.
A more interesting
questions concern the difference between a fatalistic world of
Spinoza and a world created by a wise God. At first sight it appears
quite incomprehensible how one could even confuse the two. After all,
Spinoza's world is necessary and only that is possible what happens
within that world – there is then nothing truly contingent, because
all things follow necessarily from the very necessity of God and
therefore only a person with inadequate information could call things
contingent. Wolffian God, on the other hand, can think of true
alternative possibilities and chooses one of them as the world to be
created. Hence, even if the laws of Wolff's actual world are just as
unbreakable as in Spinoza's necessary world, these laws are still
contingent according to a more extensive perspective – God could
have chosen other laws.
But as we saw from Lange's criticism, the true
problem lies in Wolff's notion of God. Wolff emphasizes the
understanding of God, when he describes God as a wise and intelligent
creator. But understanding is a passive capacity – when God sees
that a certain possible world is the most optimal, he cannot decide
himself what to describe as the best possible world. Thus, because
God is also good and he must automatically choose to create the best
possible world, it appears that we could replace God with a very
powerful computer that would just have enough capacity for viewing
even the smallest details of all possible worlds.
Wolff's answer is
to suggest that his opponents fall into equally ridiculous
consequences and are even closer to outright Spinozism. Wolff's point
is that if his opponents wish to de-emphasize the omniscience of
God's understanding, they must at the same time emphasize the
omnipotence of his will, that is, they must hold that divine will has
a power to do things that the divine understanding has not decreed to
be good. Now creation becomes a blind act of will – God becomes
like an unstoppable and irrational manufacturing plant that just
spurts out things without any rhyme or reason. Sure, what is produced
is in a sense contingent, but because of the omnipotency of creator,
the world feels like it is governed by a rigid necessity – and this
time there's not even the justification that this is all for the
best.
The struggle
between Wolff and his supposed opponents circles then around the
question whether the freedom of God, and indeed, any conscious being,
falls more to his will or to his understanding. In a sense, it is
quite obvious that it is our capacity to choose that makes us free –
if we could just watch what happens, without having the ability to
affect anything, we would not be truly free. Yet, as Wolff among
other philosophers has pointed out, mere blind will without
understanding is equally not free – after all, we wouldn't call a
machine that works on randomly generated numbers a free person. It
appears then that both understanding and will are required for the
possibility of truly free decisions; I shall not pursue the question
how to unify the two faculties into a coherent whole.
So much for the
question of necessity. Next, we'll have a short detour on Chinese
philosophy.
tiistai 1. tammikuuta 2013
Johann Joachim Lange: Humble and detailed research of the false and corruptive philosophy in Wolffian metaphysical system on God, the world, and the men; and particularly of the so-called pre-established harmony of interaction between soul and body: as also in the morals based on such system: together with a historical preface on that what happened with its author in Halle: among treatises of many important matters, and with short check on remarks concerning duplicated doubts on Wolffian philosophy - Infinite computer
We might state Lange's main criticism
of Wolffian theology quite simply: God has very little to do in
Wolff's system. True, Wolff does admit that God exists and even
proves his existence, but Lange cannot even commend Wolff's proof,
which he deems to be faulty. Indeed, Lange hits on a crucial defect.
Wolff's principle of sufficient reason or ground states that all
things should have some ground, that is, all physical things should
derive from a previous cause and all conscious actions should be
somehow motivated. From this principle Wolff suddenly moves to a
stronger principle that all things should have a full ground, that
is, they should be based on an ultimate ground that requires no
further ground for its existence. Lange notes that Wolff's original
principle of sufficient ground is consistent with an infinite causal
series bringing about the current event, thus, making the leap to the stronger principle unjustified.
Even if Wolff does accept God, Lange
continues, Wolff's deterministic world system leaves almost no room
for divine push on events. Wolff does make a halfhearted attempt to
explain the possibility of miracles: God can supernaturally affect
world, if he then makes another miracle that corrects the world so
that it will once again return to its deterministic course. In
effect, miracles of Wolffian God can make nothing new happen, because
their results are erased by the second miracle of restitution.
Lange is especially opposed to Wolff's
notion of what God is like. Wolff defines God as an entity that can
think of all infinitely multiple possible worlds. God is then meant
to choose one of these possible worlds for actualization – thus, he
does not truly create the world, Lange says, meaning perhaps that God
does not design the world from scratch, but accepts the world from a
ready-made brochure of possible worlds. Even this choice is less of
an achievement than it seems, because God is essentially a passively
cognizing entity without any spontaneous volitions. God is like a
computer that has been programmed to choose the best possible
world – God as perfectly good cannot really choose any other
option. Hence, the supposed choice becomes a mere justification of
the goodness of the actual world – creation is as deterministic as
the world created.
An atheist would then have no
difficulties in accepting Wolffian philosophy, Lange concludes, for
the assumption of God is mere play of words. Indeed, Lange thinks,
Wolff even defends atheists by saying that atheism is compatible with
morality. We shall see next time in more detail what Lange has to say
about Wolffian ethics.
keskiviikko 14. marraskuuta 2012
Christian Wolff: Reasonable thoughts on the purposes of natural things (1724)
16th of March, 1938. Two uniformed
men are walking through Vienna. They knock on a door and ask the
housekeeper to let them in. Noting the telltale swastika on their
clothes, she refuses to let them in – her employer has Jewish
roots. The arguments grows louder, but then a voice is heard above:
”Watch out!” Pedestrians quickly disperse, and the body of a
scholar of Novalis, obese cabaret actor and dilettante historian hits
ground. Egon Friedell has died.
This story, told in a preface for
Friedell's magnum opus, the three-part cultural history of modern
age, awoke my interest to the book itself in my youth. Friedell is
not viewed as particularly reliable source these days, but his style
is memorable. He was an enthusiastic admirer of such great
philosophers like Leibniz, Hegel and especially Kant, and it was
Friedell who particularly made me fall in love with classical German
philosophy.
This is the stuff that stories are made
of. Without his grim death, I might never have read Friedell's books,
thus, I might never had dedicated myself to German idealism and this
blog might have never existed. The events have a distinct end which
makes sense of everything leading to it and in a sense even justifies
all the grim details. Such a chain of events makes one ask whether it
might have been planned all along.
Such considerations drive teleological
explanations, which purport to explain what happens through what
derived of it. Of course, one might always suggest that such
explanations reflect more our expectations than anything in the
world, but the criticism can be argued against through the very same
means – if we believe that there are purposeful events, then we
will probably see them everywhere, but if we believe that there are
no purposeful events, then we will describe apparent purposeful
events as mere coincidences, even if they would really be purposeful.
It is apparent that at least human
behaviour involves purposiveness, and thus it becomes as no surprise
that I chose to begin this text with a reference to Friedell - I had a distinct purpose in my mind, when I did this. As it
happens, Friedell was also my first source on Christian Wolff, whom
Friedell ridicules as a philosopher obsessed with teleology: night exists so that we can sleep and fish, but Moon exists so that it wouldn't be too dark even at night. So far
I had not yet found any corroboration of Friedell's characterization, but the
current book,Vernünfftige Gedancken von den Absichten der
natürlichen Dingen, is
especially a work dedicated to teleology.
Nowadays
it is thought a sound scientific methodology to avoid teleological
explanations and idea of natural purpose, and therefore a whole book
dedicated to teleology will probably appear ridiculous. Yet, teleological
explanations might not be completely unscientific. Witness, for
instance, Aristotle's Physics,
which contains a reference to an end as one sort of cause. What
Aristotle means is that when things are left to their own devices,
they tend to move toward certain stable condition – for instance, a
rock falls to the ground, where it will rest. Thing in a stable
condition might not be completely inactive, in so far as their
activities are stable: Aristotelian examples of such stable actions
include recurring movement of stars and ongoing processes of living
organisms. All in all, Aristotelian teleology might involve then
nothing else, but a supposition of the existence of such stable
conditions of things.
Wolffian teleology
cannot be reinterpreted in a similar manner, because the supposed end
of e.g. metals lies not in their own nature, but in their various
uses in human culture. Instead, Wolffian teleology is essentially a
technological undertaking – Wolff describes how we can use metals
to produce kitchenware, weapons, scientific instruments and so on.
This is nothing but applied science, we could say.
What
goes beyond applied science is the assumption that things in general are
useful for technological purposes – this in an attitude justified
by Wolff's metaphysical theory of gracious, wise and powerful God.
What appeared particularly unconvincing to Friedell in this attitude
was the idea that humans especially are the central beings whom all
other things should serve – even all the stars in the sky exist
only to help navigation.
This apparent
anthropocentricity is explained by a metaphysical assumption of Wolff
– every object contains in a sense the whole world in itself, in
other words, an individual is so closely interconnected with the
world around it that neither could exist without the other. Thus, in
a sense we could take any object of the world as its central or most
essential object. For instance, we could view Earth as the most important
place in the whole universe, but for equally good reasons also
Jupiter or an arbitrary planet in the Andromeda galaxy fit the bill.
In other words all things are both means and final purposes.
This principle of a
reciprocal purposefulness allows Wolff to enlarge our knowledge
beyond what we can immediately experience. If all heavenly objects
and their occupants are final purposes, these objects must have the
necessary means for fulfilling the purposes of the occupants – they
must have oceans, an atmosphere etc. This is a place where Wolff
clearly breaks the limits of the acceptable use of teleology, and as
the moon landings have shown, there are heavenly objects that are
very inimical to life.
(Well, unless the stories of moon landings weren't just clever government tricks meant to confuse
people. We might passingly note how all conspiracy theories
resemble a sort of negative teleology – the conspiracy theorist
believes that all negative events are the result of an evil person
with almost divine capacities. No wonder one favorite Moriarty of at
least Christian conspiracy theorists is the Devil, who is apparently
out there to make us all atheists.)
Wolff does also
admit a more substantial centrality in teleology. Inorganic objects
exist only as tools for organic objects, and furthermore, irrational
organisms exist only for the sake of rational beings – human beings
are at least the most essential entities on Earth. The most crucial
question is undoubtedly then what these rational entities are
supposed to do. According to Wolff, the main aim of the rational
entities is to witness the existence of God and particularly his
goodness, wisdom and power – he has the will to create the best
possible world, he knows what it's like and then just creates such a
world. Like a small child, the omnipotent God requires an audience to praise his
achievements, we might ironically say.
So much for teleology, next time we
shall see whether Wolff's philosophy can hold on against a thorough
attack.
tiistai 14. elokuuta 2012
Johann Joachim Lange: Reasons for God and natural religion against atheism, and, all those who produce, or promote, ancient or recent pseudophilosophy, especially Stoicism and Spinozism, and principles of genuine true philosophy entwined with demonstrative method (1723)
1723 was a turning point in Christian
Wolff's career. Until then, he had spent relatively uneventful life
as a professor in the university of Halle, writing immensely popular
text books on nearly everything. In the conservative atmosphere of
German philosophy, Wolff's philosophy was not universally
appreciated, and accusations of atheist tendencies were made by his
pietist competitors – rather unexpected of a philosopher who had
dedicated a significant portion of his major work to God.
Slander is one thing, but the rumours
were starting to worry Friedrich Wilhelm I, the king of Prussia. King
was a collector, not of stamps or coins, but of big men, which were
conscripted by king's officers, by hook or by crook. Story goes that
king Friedrich Wilhem was rather worried about the supposed fatalism
of Wolff's philosophy. If all events followed strict necessity, the
men in king's collection would not be accountable for what they did –
especially if they happened to desert the army. Fearing of the fate of
his personal toys, if such terrible ideas would spread, king promptly decided
to dismantle Wolff's professorship. Fortunately Wolff quickly landed
on a new position at the university of Marburg.
The controversy around Wolff's
philosophy continued for a while, and it is on this context that we
have to evaluate Johann Joachim Lange's breathtakingly titled Caussa
Dei et religionis naturalis adversus atheismum, et, quae eum gignit,
aut promovet, pseudophilosophiam veterum et recentiorum, praesertim
Stoicam et Spinozianam, e genuinis verae philosophia principiis
methodo demonstrativa adserta.
We have already met Lange's pietistically oriented philosophy and his
attitudes towards atheism should come as no surprise – atheism is
wrong, contradictory and against morality.
The dislike of Spinoza and his geometrical method was a common theme for more religious thinkers. Indeed, Lange
begins by explicitly noting that the use of mathematical method
without any guidance might lead one to atheism – if one did not
listen to the warnings of common sense, one could stubbornly follow a
train of thought leading to absurd conclusions. One can detect a
clear sarcasm in Lange's choice of presenting the book in the very
same geometrical style of definitions, axioms and propositions to be
proved – particularly as some of the axioms and postulates he
chooses are later proven as propositions. This is not a
foundationalist attempt of building the whole edifice on an
unshakable basis, but a coherentist attempt to show how all the
jigsaw pieces fit in to form a larger picture.
The structure of
the book is thus twofold. First, Lange moves from certain common
sense assumptions to the existence of God. Here the mediating link is
provided by the notorious cosmological proof. But Lange is not
satisfied to use it once, but repeats the same form over and over
again with different topics. A soul of the human being cannot be
material, thus, it must have been fashioned by God, but the same goes
for human body and the whole human race, and indeed, the whole
material universe, which just cannot be grounded in nothing.
The pivotal point
in the deductions is human liberty. Lange's cosmological proofs that
apply to material universe hinge on the results of empirical science
and the supposed finite age of the Earth, but the proofs concerning
human soul are based on the inshakeable conviction that human soul is
free and able to control matter and therefore is irreducible to mere
matter. Furthermore, the assumption of human liberty is also behind
Lange's improved Cartesian proof. While Descartes used the presence
of the idea of God in human mind as a justification of God's
existence, Lange tries to deintellectualise this argument – human
mind is primarily will and not cognition, but because in our will we
have an impulse to know God, this impulse must come from a higher
source.
Secondly,
Lange then uses the supposedly established existence of God as a
justification of further propositions, which include also the fact of
human liberty – one of the supposed axioms of Lange. Lange's proof
of human liberty hinges on God's role as a judge that will evaluate
the worth of every human being. Lange points out that such evaluation
would be meaningless, unless the evaluated persons have a liberty to
choose their own actions – thus, God must have created human beings
as free agents.
It is
obvious that human liberty is then crucial to Lange. Without it most
of the proofs for God's existence would fall down – or at least
they wouldn't lead to a sort of God that Lange is looking for, but to
a fatalistic world soul. Indeed, it appears that when Lange is
attacking atheism, his true target is the deterministic and
mechanistic worldview of new philosophy. Human liberty is the highest ground of human
existence and those who dare to deny it are miserable people, because
they contradict the natural certainty of their own freedom. The topic
of human liberty is also where Lange's grudge against Wolffian
philosophy becomes clear. Wolff's endorsement of Leibnizian
pre-established harmony breaks the required connection between the
soul and the body: soul only appears to control body, which is
actually moving according to its own laws.
One
could even say that the battle against atheism has always been a
battle for human liberty. Nowadays hardcore atheists feel great
pleasure in pointing out faults in creation science. Yet, the kernel
of a religion is not constituted by any dogmas, but by rituals and
cults. Denial of God appears to leave no room for an objective
meaning of life and hence deprives world of all magic. Even pantheism
is suspected, because it reeks of closet atheism.
So much
for Lange, next time I'll take a look at a philosophical dispute for
the first time in this blog.
maanantai 18. kesäkuuta 2012
Barthold Heinrich Brockes: Earthly delight in God, consisting of various poems taken from nature and ethics, together with an addendum containing some relevant translations of French fables of Mr. de la Motte (1721)
At the very beginning of my blog I
expressly noted that I should avoid works of fiction and poetry,
because I felt I would have little to say about such manners. Yet, I
also admitted that in some case I surely had to do it, if the thinker
in question had written mainly fictional works – no matter how
inconsequential the thinker might seem.
Barthold Heinrich Brockes is probably
not the most important German thinker of his time. He was educated in
the Thomasian school of philosophy, but unlike the other Thomasians
we have met so far, he wasn't an ardent enemy of Wolffians. Instead,
Brockes could be best described as a thinker of Aufklärung,
or German enlightenment, and hence, his inclusion in the blog
broadens our view of German philosophical culture in early 18th
century.
When one hears of
enlightenment, one is bound to think of Voltaire, Diderot, Rousseau
and others rather radical thinkers, who at least influenced the later
revolutionists in France. But the German enlightenment was never so
radical and most of the times it was never as critical of church as
French enlighteners were. Instead, German enlightenment was all about
the education of mankind – and in this case, education was meant to
include also moral instruction. We have already seen such tendencies
in Wolff, particularly in his insistence that all art must serve the
use of upholding morality in state.
Now,
the work of Brockes is almost a paradigmatic example of Wolff's
suggestion. Brockes was known as a translator, and even the book
Irdisches Vergnügen in Gott bestehend in verschiedenen aus
der natur und Sitten-Lehre hergenommenen Gedichten, nebst einem
Anhange etlicher hieher gehörigen Uebersetzungen von Hrn. de la
Motte Französisch. Fabeln contains,
as the title says, translations of few French fables. Furthermore,
Brockes himself was a poet, and the book I have been reading now is
also a book of poetry.
Brockes' place in
the history of German literature is far from glorious, which one
wouldn't believe from reading the preface that praises the talents of
Brockes both as a translator and as a poet. What is interesting is
the explanation what makes Brockes a poet among poets. Apparently the
author has not only the imagination required for creating dazzling
images, but also the understanding required for making his poems well
ordered and something more than just incomprehensible mess. This
interplay of imagination and understanding was more
generally held to be a precondition of good poetry and art. Something
similar can be seen even seen in Kant's notion of beauty as caused by
the free play of faculties, although there it is more about
experiencing than creating beauty.
I shall briefly
describe one exemplary piece of this poet-to-be. The poem with the
ominous title ”the world” begins with the image of people
watching the world, as it were, through the wrong end of the
telescope: everything looks much smaller than it really is. For
instance, a businessman sees nothing but profits and losses, while a
doctor sees nothing else but illness and cures. Even philosopher
fairs badly, because he sees nothing else but planets circling around
the sun – Brockes is probably thinking of works like Newton's
natural philosophy. Among these failed attempts to understand the
world, there is one who does it right – the dreamer who sees God in
all phenomena of nature.
This
exemplary poem shows already Brockes' fascination with nature. Most
of his poems simply describe some natural event, like the awakening
of animals in spring, thunderstorm or sun. But nature is not
described in these poems as an entity deserving an independent
account. Instead, the worth of all these events is that they reveal
the power of God – the nature is a piece of art and behind this art
there must be some artist.
In a
sense, Brockes' poetry is nothing more than constant use of
teleological argumentation deducing from the perfection of natural
objects the existence of their creator. Yet, it is not any arguments,
but the sentiment behind this statement that is important. To find
perfection in the colour of grass and in rain falling from the sky,
and not just any perfection, but a feeling of divine serenity and
splendour – this is what Brockes is trying to convey. The enjoyment
of nature was even an international phenomenon during 18th
century, and in Germany it finally culminated with the pantheistic
tendencies of romantic school, in which God and nature were often
regarded as opposed, but still related poles.
One may feel that
such a pantheistic appreciation of nature is far from theistic
delight with nature, yet, at least this underlying feeling of the
divinity of natur is shared by both alike. For a pantheist the
splendour of nature is a part of the nature, while for a theist the
perfection must originate somewhere beyond nature. The official credo
at the time was theistic, both in Wolffian and Thomasian schools,
latter of which will be my topic next time.
perjantai 10. helmikuuta 2012
Christian Wolff: Reasonable thoughts on God, world, and human soul, furthermore, of all things in general - The ultimate thing
When one for the first time hears
Leibnizian principle of sufficient reason, it seems quite obvious and
self-evident: of course, everything happens for a reason. But as
Samuel Clarke was quick to notice, the innocent appearing principle
could be used for smuggling substantial presuppositions behind our backs. For
instance, Leibniz himself used the principle to justify the more
uncertain principle of the identity of indiscernibles: God could not have created two exactly similar things, because God would have no ground for choosing the situations of the two things.
Wolff begins the chapter on natural
theology by a similar abuse of the principle of sufficient reason.
Theology itself is probably a familiar term to everyone, but what
makes it natural? The answer is that natural theology is supposedly
based on mere human reason, while the other type of theology – that
is, revealed – is based on supposed divine revelation.
Wolff thus supposes that a sufficient
reason is only such that requires no reason beyond itself. In effect,
Wolff has not been demanding just an explanation, but a full
explanation of everything, ending with a final term that is
self-explanatory. And as we might remember from previous texts,
Wolffian ground/reason is not just any explanation, but a causal
agent actualising things. The principle of the sufficient reason is
hence suddenly turned into a commitment for the existence of a final
instigator of causal things. That is, to a commitment that while
normal possible things require some external force to overcome the
opposite possibility of their non-existence, there is a thing that
has enough force in itself for self-actualisation.
It takes no theologian to guess that
this self-actualising thing, which cannot fail to exist, is meant to
be the traditional God: a transcendent being beyond both the physical
world and the realm of human souls. One might still wonder why Wolff
accepts only a single self-actualising thing. After all, the causal
chains in the world might have more than one beginning, that is,
there might well be more than one God.
Although Wolff does not directly answer
this problem, he does try to argue against the identification of
humans and God on the basis of the possible multiplicity of human
souls. Wolff notes that when one accepts the existence of the world,
it is easy to see that the human soul as dependent on the world
cannot be God. Idealists, who deny the existence of the world,
and even what Wolff calls egoists and what we would call solipsists, that is, philosophers admitting only their own existence, admit at least that there are many possible human souls. Yet, just
this plurality of souls makes it impossible that the humans would be
Gods. Plurality of possible Gods is apparently against the necessity
of the supposed God: if a thing might be otherwise and still a God,
it would require a further ground why the thing then is like it
actually is, thus, it surely couldn't be self-actualising and
self-explaining.
When it comes to God's characteristics,
Wolff follows tradition: God is, for instance, capable of intuiting
all things immediately, thus, requires no symbolic knowledge; he is
wise, that is, capable of planning the relationships between the
things in the most perfect manner possible; he also lives in the
highest possible bliss, because he sees the perfection of the world.
But what interests us most is the relationship between the God and
the world.
Until now, the status of the
possibilities or essences in Wolffian philosophy has been rather
unclear: on the one hand, essences are said to be eternal and thus existing, on the
other hand, they are not actualised. Wolff suggests that it is the
understanding of God that sustains all the various possibilities:
they exist in a sense, because God is continuously thinking all of
them.
Although God thinks all the
possibilities and especially all possible worlds, this does not still
make them actual. Instead, actuality is received through a force,
which is external, if the actualised thing is not God, and
ultimately, through God’s will.
Interestingly, this characterisation is
connected to Wolff’s notion of philosophy as a science of
possibilities. Although the understanding of humans is not as pure as
God’s – that is, it is confused or sensous – we can at least
partially follow what is going on in God’s understanding, because
the content of his understanding is necessary: that is, there can be
no other possibilities. Then again, what is actual depends on God’s
choice and the motives behind it. Thus, we can know generally that
God has chosen the best possible world, but we cannot with certainty
say that a particular chain of events would belong to the best
possible world – in other words, there cannot be any true science
of actualities.
*******************************************************************************
Because I have finally reached the end
of Wolff’s German Magnum Opus, this is a great opportunity to
evaluate the whole book. The historical worth of Wolff’s German
metaphysics is unquestionable. Although there had been philosophical
books written in German, Wolff’s book was still the most systematic
treatment of all the major topics of traditional metaphysics, and as
we shall most likely see in the distant future, its influence can
still be felt in Kant’s writings. That said, we might still
question the originality of his work in a wider perspective of the
Europian philosophy in 18th century: I shall say a little bit
about this topic in the next post.
Does German metaphysics then hold any
interest for a modern philosopher? As we have witnessed, the book is
full of gaps in argumentation, unwarranted presuppositions and plain
sophisms. Still, one must appreciate at least the architectural
design of the book, where in the ontology the classification into
three main types of things – complex or material things and
especially the world, simle, but finite things and especially souls,
and the infinite thing or God – is introduced and where the final
chapter ties all the knots by showing how both the material world and
the souls are dependent on the God.
Wolff's German metaphysics has finally
ended. I have been rather longwinded on the topic, but I have felt
this has been necessary, because of the historical importance of the
book. Next time, I shall make a short detour on an earlier
philosopher: we shall meet the supposed predecessor of Wolff.
Tilaa:
Blogitekstit (Atom)