In the previous post I mentioned the conflict, which Gottsched had with the Swiss aestheticians Bodmer and Breitinger. In retrospect, this conflict was less to do with completely different notions of aesthetics and more to do with different emphasis: Gottsched was more keen to hold on to the principle of the imitation of nature and clear rules derived from this principle, while Bodmer and Breitinger thought wonder to be the essential element of aesthetic feeling. While previously we saw Bodmer's practical application of their notion of aesthetics, Breitinger's Critische Dichtkunst presents its basic theory.
One must at first note that despite Breitinger's animosity with Gottsched, he doesn't wonder too far from tenets of Wolffian philosophy. Thus, we hear philosophy or ”worldly wisdom” defined as a science of all things, in so far as humans are capable of knowing the ground of their possibility and actuality.
What Breitinger wants to modify in Wolff's philosophy is to add rhetoric and poetry as its parts. His justification is based purely on utilitarian grounds. While philosophy is based on intricate scientific reasoning, most people simply cannot follow it and they have to be educated by other needs, that is, with the help of rhetoric and poetry.
Furthermore, Breitinger also accepts the suggestion that poetry is imitation of nature. That is not to say that poetry would be just a retelling of what happens in world around us, somewhat like history. Instead, poetry should arouse a feeling of truth in its reader through sensuous images. In this sense, poetry resembles painting, which also tries to imitate nature by creating a semblance of truth in its watcher. Yet, painting affects us more forcefully, while poetry has the advantage in being able to use material from all senses, which is just recollected by hearing certain words.
Since Breitinger accepts the idea that the actual world is the best of all possible worlds, he is bound to accept that imitated natural things can be regarded good. Yet, Breitinger finds a certain difference – while the goodness of the actual world is intrinsic to it, goodness of poems lies in them being good imitations. Thus, one can have a good poem, even if its topic falls short of complete perfection.
As it was habit with Gottsched and Bodmer, Breitinger extends the notion of imitation from the actual to all possible worlds, and just like Bodmer, he extends it quite far, to improbable possibilities, in which animals and plants speak and all sorts of allegorical abstractions exist. Indeed, such fables are one end of poetic works, in which wondrous rules over probability. Still, even they have some share of probability, since human mind has the tendency to antropomorphise natural things and especially animals.
In general, Breitinger sees all poetic works balancing between wonder and probability. Too much of wonder and a poem loses its credibility. Then again, too little of wonder and a reader won't have any interest on the poem. Most of the art of poetics deals then with various ways to enhance both wonder and probability. Thus, even when describing quite ordinary things, poet can highlight some of their more extraordinary properties or show them in an unexpected light. Similarly, one must make e.g. actions and speeches of a person seem like they would flow naturally out of the character of the person.
I will not go further into the petty details of the conflict between Gottsched and Breitinger/Bodmer-duo, and hence, this will be last we'll hear of any of them. Next time, I shall look at a completely different discipline, namely, jurisprudence.
Näytetään tekstit, joissa on tunniste poetry. Näytä kaikki tekstit
Näytetään tekstit, joissa on tunniste poetry. Näytä kaikki tekstit
tiistai 6. syyskuuta 2016
torstai 23. kesäkuuta 2016
Bodmer: Critical inquiry on wondrous in poetry (1740)
It is always refreshing to see a philosopher reconsider his old ideas and to move away from positions he held earlier. This appears to be case with Bodmer, whose earlier work showed clear influences of Wolffian philosophy and regarded imitation as the basic principle of good poetry. By the time of writing his Critische Abhandlung von dem Wunderbaren in der Poesie und dessen Verbindung mit dem Wahrscheinlichen, Bodmer appears to have changed his opinion quite radically – art need not be limited by correspondence with actual objects, because in addition to actual world, poems can deal also with other possible worlds.
The topic of Bodmer's work is John Milton's Paradise Lost, a poem about the rebellion of Satan against God and of the fall of the first human beings from the grace. A number of French critics had attacked the book, notably because it had tried to overreach the limit of what is humanly imaginable and to describe things no human being could have ever witnessed. A good example is provided by the angels. Critics had complained that these are actually immaterial entities, but Milton describes them as having flesh and blood. When it comes to fallen angels, he even suggests they can feel bodily pain. Bodmer notes that Milton is just following an age-old tradition – even Homeric gods had a body, were bodily exhausted etc. Furthermore, he notes that a poet can refrain from literal imitation, if a powerful allegory demands it.
Even further in his dismissal of the principle of imitation Bodmer goes when he speaks of Milton's use of such entities like Death and Sin. The French critics had complained that these characters felt quite shadowy and that their presence in the poem mad the whole thing look quite improbable. Bodmer notes that a poet need not restrict oneself to mere probabilities, when the whole range of possibilities is available for him – and who can tell what wonders lie in the immaterial world?
Bodmer's aesthetical bent drives him then toward extending the range of what can be recounted in a work of fiction – not just probabilities, but also possibilities. This attack against very restricted theories of imitation is not the only philosophically interesting theme Bodmer considers. For instance, he notes that when Milton describes Satan as having momentary relief from pain, the poet is just telling the truth, since an infinite amount of pain is impossible for a limited entity, which even an angel must be. Or, when critics express puzzlement that Adam could know concepts of negative emotions, when all he had thus far had were positive emotions, Bodmer notes that Adam could well have abstracted the concept of a negative emotion from his experience of positive emotions – it wouldn't have been a distinct concept, but it would still have been a concept. Yet, the main aesthetic innovation of the work is just this attack on imitation as the sole principle of poetry.
Although Bodmer speaks of French critics, another probable target of his attack is Gottschedian school of aesthetics, in which naturalness was seen as the central element of poetry – so central that even operas were thought to be bad poetry, because people singing all the time is just artificial construct. Indeed, Bodmer's work can be seen as an integral part of his conflict with Gottsched, which was an important source of controversy in the 1740s. We shall have occasion to speak about this controversy with the next book, which was written by Johann Jakob Breitinger, an ally of Bodmer.
The topic of Bodmer's work is John Milton's Paradise Lost, a poem about the rebellion of Satan against God and of the fall of the first human beings from the grace. A number of French critics had attacked the book, notably because it had tried to overreach the limit of what is humanly imaginable and to describe things no human being could have ever witnessed. A good example is provided by the angels. Critics had complained that these are actually immaterial entities, but Milton describes them as having flesh and blood. When it comes to fallen angels, he even suggests they can feel bodily pain. Bodmer notes that Milton is just following an age-old tradition – even Homeric gods had a body, were bodily exhausted etc. Furthermore, he notes that a poet can refrain from literal imitation, if a powerful allegory demands it.
Even further in his dismissal of the principle of imitation Bodmer goes when he speaks of Milton's use of such entities like Death and Sin. The French critics had complained that these characters felt quite shadowy and that their presence in the poem mad the whole thing look quite improbable. Bodmer notes that a poet need not restrict oneself to mere probabilities, when the whole range of possibilities is available for him – and who can tell what wonders lie in the immaterial world?
Bodmer's aesthetical bent drives him then toward extending the range of what can be recounted in a work of fiction – not just probabilities, but also possibilities. This attack against very restricted theories of imitation is not the only philosophically interesting theme Bodmer considers. For instance, he notes that when Milton describes Satan as having momentary relief from pain, the poet is just telling the truth, since an infinite amount of pain is impossible for a limited entity, which even an angel must be. Or, when critics express puzzlement that Adam could know concepts of negative emotions, when all he had thus far had were positive emotions, Bodmer notes that Adam could well have abstracted the concept of a negative emotion from his experience of positive emotions – it wouldn't have been a distinct concept, but it would still have been a concept. Yet, the main aesthetic innovation of the work is just this attack on imitation as the sole principle of poetry.
Although Bodmer speaks of French critics, another probable target of his attack is Gottschedian school of aesthetics, in which naturalness was seen as the central element of poetry – so central that even operas were thought to be bad poetry, because people singing all the time is just artificial construct. Indeed, Bodmer's work can be seen as an integral part of his conflict with Gottsched, which was an important source of controversy in the 1740s. We shall have occasion to speak about this controversy with the next book, which was written by Johann Jakob Breitinger, an ally of Bodmer.
maanantai 16. maaliskuuta 2015
Baumgarten: Chorographic dissertation, evolving notions of superior and inferior, ascending and descending, which occur in sacred chorography and Uninsignificant philosophical meditations concerning poems (1735)
![]() |
Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten, 1714 - 1762 |
When Wolff left his
post in Halle because of the atheism controversy, a philosophical
vacuum was all that left. Around the end of 1730s this vacuum was finally
filled by a new eminent figure, Alexander Baumgarten. It is two early
pieces of Baumgarten I am looking at in this post.
The first of these
works, Dissertatio chorographica, Notiones
superi et inferi, indeque adscensus et descensus, in chorographiis
sacris occurentes, evolvens does not deserve a careful
study, because it is mainly of historical worth as Baumgarten's
dissertation. It is not so much a philosophical, but a theological
study of the presence of notions like superior and inferior or ascend
and descend in the Bible. Baumgarten's main point is that while the
words have a literal meaning of higher and lower or moving to a
higher place and moving to a lower place, the words are also used in
a figurative sense: superior is not just physically higher place, but
better, just like Heaven is superior to Earth and Earth superior to
Hell.
Somewhat more
interesting is Baumgarten's work on poetry, Meditationes
philosophicae de nonnullis ad poema pertinentibus, especially as
Baumgarten was later known as the instigator of aesthetical studies –
indeed, the word aesthetics itself is already used in this early
work. Baumgarten shows his clear Wolffian heritage especially in his
manner of carefully defining all the terms he uses in his discussion.
Thus, we hear that oration, for instance, is a series of sounds which
are connected with some significance – ”Peter picked a pickled
penny” is so an oration, because it consists of certain
combinations of sounds that have a meaning. As these combinations or
words have representations as their significance, orations reveal
certain connections between representations.
In poetry, then, the
words signify usually sensuous representations, that is,
representations belonging to what in Wolffian psychology is taken as
an inferior faculty of representation. Of course, even quite prosaic
sentences fall under that description – ”Cat is sitting on a mat”
is not a true poem, but it still refers to sensitive representations
of things like cat, Poetry is differentiated from such sensitive
representations by being more perfect – perfection means here
especially that poems reveal more connections between various
sensuous representations.
This rather
summarised ideal of a poem leads then to various principles of a good
poem – these principles or rules then constitute poetics. Poems
themselves, like all orations, contain three distinct features: the
words themselves as mere sounds, the significance of the words or
representations and their connections. Starting with the first
feature, the words as mere sounds are important only as producing
sensuous pleasure – thus, poems are expected to have pleasing
rhythm and soothing melody.
Most of Baumgarten's
rules concern representations or their connections. Thus, we hear
Baumgarten pronouncing that representations occasioned by poems must
be more vivid than other orations. Thus, these representations must
feature as many aspects of the topic of the poem as possible. Indeed,
the height of poetic perfection is to characterise a complete, living
individual in her full personality.
A somewhat striking
consequence of the demand of vivacity or clarity of representations
occasioned by poetry is that an attempt to go too much into the realm
of fantasy leads to less poetic verses – after all, mere
imaginations seem less vivid than things that we could actually
sense. Mere utopias and impossibilities are not poetic at all,
although internal consistency and coherence might help (thus,
Tolkien's well structured world might still deserve the name of
poetry). Instead of fantasy, the kernel of poetic lies according to
Baumgarten in metaphors, which show deep and unnoticable connections
between different representations.
So much for
Baumgarten's first writings. Next time I'll return to Wolff's
opponents.
lauantai 16. elokuuta 2014
Attempt at a critical art of poetry (1730)
We have already witnessed an uprising
of a Wolffian school, particularly in the guise of two followers of
Wolff, Thümmig and Bilfinger, but now a second generation of
Wolffians starts to appear on the scene of German philosophy. Johann
Christoph Gottsched had already studied Thümmig's summarised
rendering of Wolff's ideas and would himself write another text book
of philosophy later in 1730s. Yet, his primary achievements on the
field of philosophy was the introduction of aesthetical questions to
German philosophy in the shape of a widely distributed book, Versuch
einer critischen Dichtkunst.
![]() |
Gottsched (1700-1766) |
As the name of the work reveals, its
topic is the art of poetry and particularly the possibility of
evaluating poetic works through philosophical principles. As we shall
see again when considering Gottsched's text book on general
philosophy, he was quite fond of beginning with historical
discussions and especially with speculations on times before reliable
written histories. Thus, he suggests that poetry is the second eldest
art, preceded only by music, which also was a natural ingredient in
the first works of poetry, which were sang and not read.
At first poems were made
quite freely, Gottsched continues, but experience made it clear that
even poetry must have some rules – he explicitly mentions Aristotle
and Horace as masters in this field. Every art, Gottsched suggests,
strives to imitate nature – painting does it with images and music
with sounds, but poetry can use full field of all sensations, or at
least our mental recollections of such sensations. Just like every
other art, poetry must then strive for naturalness, Gottsched
concludes.
Mere description of natural entities is
still not poetry, according to Gottsched, or at least it occupies
only the lowest rung. A slightly more adequate type imitates the
speech patterns of certain persons – this is especially true of
dramatic works. Yet, the real meat of poetry lies in fables or story
telling – a good poem tells of activities of people, either of the
common folk, as in comedies, or of the noble and mighty, as in
tragedies or in epics, which Gottsched evaluates as the highest form
of poetry, recounting an event important to the fate of a whole
nation. It is clear without saying that Gottsched insists each story
to have a moral – the aim of poetry is to make people better.
Gottsched accepts the Wolffian
idea that stories present, as it were, events in other possible
worlds and thus might not follow rules of the actual world – a
story might have, for instance, talking animals as characters. Still, naturalness
is an important standard for good poetry: improbable events usually
hinder the enjoyment of a poem, Gottsched says. Of course, what seems
probable depends on the level of education. We cannot therefore
disparage Greeks for using divinities and other mythical entities as
characters, but in the modern world any use of magical effects would
seem incredible, Gottsched concludes.
Even if Gottsched strives for
naturalism, when it comes to stories, he does not insist on using a
natural style in poems. Indeed, he goes even so far as to suggest
that too naturalist style might turn into banalities, which are
against morality. In fact, poetic style is characterised by certain
wittiness, which combines seemingly distant ideas in a manner that is
rare in a straightforward historical telling of events: thus, while a
historical work describing a battle would just recount all the
events, a poem about the same battle might e.g. use some suggestive
similes making more philosophical points about the nature of warfare.
A good poet is then one who can
discover new and surprising connections between apparently quite
disparate topics. Yet, this is still not enough, Gottsched says. An
uneducated natural poet does not know about the rules of good poetry
and therefore might well fail to have a proper taste and be lured by
bad novels. Even if she manages to gain skills required for good
poetry, she might still lack the basic ethical education, which is an
essential requirement for educational poetry.
Judging just by these general
directives, one might concur with Egon Friedell that Gottsched was a
bit uptight in his aesthetic views. This impression is amply
confirmed by his actual reviews of certain well known poets.
Shakespeare's Julius Caesar
has some delightful moments, Gottsched admits, but it has one great
fault – the events of the play last longer than one day, which
makes the whole thing seem quite improbable, as what audience sees
happens only within few hours (I believe Gottsched is just one of
those persons with no ability for suspension of disbelief). And
Molière is also witty author, but he
sometimes uses characters reminiscent of commedia dell'arte
and especially that awfully unbelievable magical trickster, the
Harlequin. Besides, many of
his plays fail to have a proper moral.
But
truly vehement criticism
Gottsched lays upon opera, which
he calls the most absurd invention of human understanding.
This form of art Gottsched
considers to follow the sad tendency of modern forms of poetry that
they let the music control the substance of the poem too much. Indeed, even the very notion of opera shows its absurdity, because the idea of people singing all the time is just too incredible to believe. True,
the music can be divine, but the stories used are from the worst
kinds of books, featuring all sorts of unlikely events, magic and
wondrous things, making it all seem like a tale out of another
planet. But what is definitely worst is the complete absence of
morals that operas appear to endorse. As a life-long fan of Wagner I
cannot but wonder what Gottsched would have had to say about the
overtly
mythological story of Nibelungen.
![]() |
GOTTSCHED: Dragons? No way! |
It
is not that Gottsched sees no justification for the existence of
opera – it can serve as an amusement of princes and nobles, serving
to ease their life of constant toil over state welfare. Even here
Gottsched recommends replacing opera with ballet, which at least
reveals the gentle grace of human anatomy. After all these remarks,
one cannot fail to see the irony that a person attempting to find
universal rules of good poetry can epitomise so well the essential
relativism of aesthetic judgements.
So much for
Gottsched's aesthetics, next I shall return to Wolff with yet another
part of his Latin works.
perjantai 7. helmikuuta 2014
Reasonable thoughts and judgements on eloquence: Of influence and use of imagination for improvement of taste or detailed study of all sorts of writings (1727)
We have finally
reached a time, when Wolffians are not just content to explicate what
their master said and defend his views from attacks, but also attempt to develop
his ideas to their own direction. It was aesthetics, a matter that
Wolff himself had left almost completely unnoticed, which was the
first new field to be tackled by German philosophers.
Johann
Jakob Bodmer's appreciation of Wolff is evident even from the name of
his planned book series on poetry, Vernünfftige Gedancken
und Urtheile von den Beredsamkeit. The
series was meant to study the topic from various angles, and while
the first book, Von dem Einfluss und Gebrauche der
Einbildungs-Krafft; Zur Ausbesserung des Geschmackes: Oder Genaue
Untersuchung Aller Arten Bescreihbungen,
concentrated on imagination, the later books were meant to consider
e.g. wit, taste and sublime. As far as I know, the first book of the
projected series was also the only one ever written.
![]() |
Bodmer in his old age |
The Wolffian
leanings of Bodmer are especially revealed by his attempt to situate
aesthetics within the context of Wolffian cosmotheology. World was
meant by God as something to be studied by rational entities, that
is, human beings were meant to investigate the works of nature and thus see
the glory of its Creator. The first means by which humans get in
contact with world are senses, but with these we can merely come to
know what is directly before us.
What is at least
required for a more complex knowledge is the capacity of imagination,
which at that time meant not just a capacity for creativity, but
referred to all mental activities in which the object is not
necessarily present to our senses – the object may then well be
something that has existed and that we are only recollecting. Indeed,
it is not complete fictions imagination should try to convey, but
real things that do not happen to be present to our senses at the
moment.
Art, for Bodmer, is
then a matter of imitation – rather conservative view from modern
perspective. Among the different types of artists, poet then ranks
higher in Bodmer's view than painter or sculptor. While fine arts in
general are based on visual sensations, to which in sculpture tactile
sensations are added, poetic descriptions can use the whole range of
sensations and emotions to convey the likeness of an object. Poet
should even be master of all arts and skills, knowing everything from
anything, Bodmer concludes.
Bodmer's criterion
for good art and especially good poetry is then its capacity to evoke
realistic ideas of things it describes. The majority of the book
presents then examples of poetry, evaluated with this criterion. It
seems clear that Bodmer is clearly wanting in decent German poetic
works: when one has to elevate Brockes, rather repetitive writer of
poems evoking teleological reasoning over and over again,
as an example of what Germans can do at their best. Bodmer himself
has to confess that while German language has evocative vocabulary for
describing nature, in affairs of culture one must turn to Latin,
Italian and French poets - especially Pierre Corneille appears to have been a favourite of Bodmer's.
While then
especially many of the German works quoted by Bodmer feel rather
artificial, Bodmer's own evaluations seem also rather misplaced. We
might think it rather trite, if a writer compares lips of a woman to
Red Sea, but it feels somewhat strange to condemn the lines
containing this comparison, because Red Sea isn't actually red at
all. Yet, it falls perfectly in line with Bodmer's naturalistic ideal
of poetry. Thus, he is often disparaging unnecessary use of wit and
prefers writings that reveal actual experience of things described.
In case of human emotions, he praises writers who have clearly, for
instance, suffered the sorrow of a lost wife.
![]() |
Red Sea, not that red actually |
When giving guide
lines for poems describing human behaviour, Bodmer also touches on
some quaint philosophical notions. Physiognomy or the idea of the
character of a person showing through one's appearance is familiaralready from Wolff's writings and Bodmer himself mentions Wolff as a great source for future poets
for finding good descriptions of the external effects of human
emotions. Another rather old-fashioned idea is the notion of national
characteristics determined partly by natural environment, partly by
mores and customs of the nation – this is probably something that
we will see in more detail with later German philosophers.
So much for
Bodmerian aesthetics for now, next it is finally time to begin
Wolff's Latin works.
maanantai 18. kesäkuuta 2012
Barthold Heinrich Brockes: Earthly delight in God, consisting of various poems taken from nature and ethics, together with an addendum containing some relevant translations of French fables of Mr. de la Motte (1721)
At the very beginning of my blog I
expressly noted that I should avoid works of fiction and poetry,
because I felt I would have little to say about such manners. Yet, I
also admitted that in some case I surely had to do it, if the thinker
in question had written mainly fictional works – no matter how
inconsequential the thinker might seem.
Barthold Heinrich Brockes is probably
not the most important German thinker of his time. He was educated in
the Thomasian school of philosophy, but unlike the other Thomasians
we have met so far, he wasn't an ardent enemy of Wolffians. Instead,
Brockes could be best described as a thinker of Aufklärung,
or German enlightenment, and hence, his inclusion in the blog
broadens our view of German philosophical culture in early 18th
century.
When one hears of
enlightenment, one is bound to think of Voltaire, Diderot, Rousseau
and others rather radical thinkers, who at least influenced the later
revolutionists in France. But the German enlightenment was never so
radical and most of the times it was never as critical of church as
French enlighteners were. Instead, German enlightenment was all about
the education of mankind – and in this case, education was meant to
include also moral instruction. We have already seen such tendencies
in Wolff, particularly in his insistence that all art must serve the
use of upholding morality in state.
Now,
the work of Brockes is almost a paradigmatic example of Wolff's
suggestion. Brockes was known as a translator, and even the book
Irdisches Vergnügen in Gott bestehend in verschiedenen aus
der natur und Sitten-Lehre hergenommenen Gedichten, nebst einem
Anhange etlicher hieher gehörigen Uebersetzungen von Hrn. de la
Motte Französisch. Fabeln contains,
as the title says, translations of few French fables. Furthermore,
Brockes himself was a poet, and the book I have been reading now is
also a book of poetry.
Brockes' place in
the history of German literature is far from glorious, which one
wouldn't believe from reading the preface that praises the talents of
Brockes both as a translator and as a poet. What is interesting is
the explanation what makes Brockes a poet among poets. Apparently the
author has not only the imagination required for creating dazzling
images, but also the understanding required for making his poems well
ordered and something more than just incomprehensible mess. This
interplay of imagination and understanding was more
generally held to be a precondition of good poetry and art. Something
similar can be seen even seen in Kant's notion of beauty as caused by
the free play of faculties, although there it is more about
experiencing than creating beauty.
I shall briefly
describe one exemplary piece of this poet-to-be. The poem with the
ominous title ”the world” begins with the image of people
watching the world, as it were, through the wrong end of the
telescope: everything looks much smaller than it really is. For
instance, a businessman sees nothing but profits and losses, while a
doctor sees nothing else but illness and cures. Even philosopher
fairs badly, because he sees nothing else but planets circling around
the sun – Brockes is probably thinking of works like Newton's
natural philosophy. Among these failed attempts to understand the
world, there is one who does it right – the dreamer who sees God in
all phenomena of nature.
This
exemplary poem shows already Brockes' fascination with nature. Most
of his poems simply describe some natural event, like the awakening
of animals in spring, thunderstorm or sun. But nature is not
described in these poems as an entity deserving an independent
account. Instead, the worth of all these events is that they reveal
the power of God – the nature is a piece of art and behind this art
there must be some artist.
In a
sense, Brockes' poetry is nothing more than constant use of
teleological argumentation deducing from the perfection of natural
objects the existence of their creator. Yet, it is not any arguments,
but the sentiment behind this statement that is important. To find
perfection in the colour of grass and in rain falling from the sky,
and not just any perfection, but a feeling of divine serenity and
splendour – this is what Brockes is trying to convey. The enjoyment
of nature was even an international phenomenon during 18th
century, and in Germany it finally culminated with the pantheistic
tendencies of romantic school, in which God and nature were often
regarded as opposed, but still related poles.
One may feel that
such a pantheistic appreciation of nature is far from theistic
delight with nature, yet, at least this underlying feeling of the
divinity of natur is shared by both alike. For a pantheist the
splendour of nature is a part of the nature, while for a theist the
perfection must originate somewhere beyond nature. The official credo
at the time was theistic, both in Wolffian and Thomasian schools,
latter of which will be my topic next time.
Tilaa:
Blogitekstit (Atom)