We have been studying what Darjes calls primary philosophy, but we finally come to his ontology, when we see his definition of an entity (ens). In effect, by an entity Darjes means something that is not accident, that is, which can be in itself. What this being in itself means, according to Darjes, is at least that in the same place as one entity exists, no other entity can exist. Thus, impenetrability of an entity is an ontological characteristic for Darjes, while accidents might share the same place by occurring in same entity. An entity need not exist, but it can be a merely possible entity. If it does exist, Darjes calls it a substance.
Darjes notes that all substances can contain something which is a reason for something else being what it is. In other words, they are forces that can act on other things. Now, because this activity is an essential part of what substances are, they can also be divided according to their level of activity. The highest kind of substance is completely active and needs at most something to remove obstacles from its way to start acting – they are what Darjes calls an effective conatus. At the lowest rang of substances are completely passive substances, which require some efficient reason to make them act – these are what Darjes calls bare potentia. Between these two extremes fall cases where substances are in some sense passive and in some sense active – these substances Darjes calls either ineffective conatuses or potentias with conatus (it is difficult to say whether Darjes means these two to be separate groups, depending on whether the emphasis is on the active or the passive side of the substance or whether they are just two names for the same thing).
Darjes does not just distinguish between different kinds of forces or substances, but also between different kinds of actions these substances can make occur. The actions might happen within the substances or be intrinsic to it – these would be immanent actions. Then again, the actions might also be extrinsic to the substance – these would be transitive actions. Of course, Darjes also admits that some actions might be partially immanent and partially transitive.
Like all Wolffians, Darjes is a nominalist who insists that no universals can exist. Hence, all substances must be individuals. Although substances cannot then be divided into universals and individuals, Darjes does divide them into complete and incomplete substances, depending on whether a substance acts or not. He also notes that a substance can be variably or contingently complete, if it sometimes happens to act and sometimes not. Even if a substance would be contingently complete, it still might be a necessary existent, since there is no necessity that a necessary existent would always act.
A notion near to completeness is the subsistence of a substance. Darjes defines subsistent substance as a complete substance that is not sustained by something else. Here, sustaining means a relation in which one force determines another to act in a precise manner. Thus, subsisting substance would act and not be acted upon by other substances.
Darjes goes on to define states of an entity. In effect, these are nothing more than collections of some determinations that the entity has. For instance, being a substance or substantiality and subsistence are states that some entity might have. Depending on the determinations making up the state, the state can be internal, external or mixed, and it can be necessary or contingent. For instance, if there are some entities existing absolutely necessarily, then they have an absolutely necessary state of substantiality. With contingent entities, on the other hand, their state of substantiality is also contingent and in fact depends ultimately on some absolutely necessary substance.
Darjes does not remain on mere level of definitions, but tries to determine some general characteristics true of all substances, based mostly on the principle of sufficient reason. The most important conclusion is that all substances must persevere in their state of action or non-action, until some further reason makes them change their state. Thus, an action continues, until something comes to impede it.
Darjes also spends some time considering how to quantify forces. His idea is to measure forces through the actions they can make happen. For instance, if two passive substances have the same quantity of force is they are as quick in producing same actions, then they will produce same action in same time. Thus, by checking what the substances can achieve and how quickly they do it, one can compare the quantity of their forces with one another.
Näytetään tekstit, joissa on tunniste individuals. Näytä kaikki tekstit
Näytetään tekstit, joissa on tunniste individuals. Näytä kaikki tekstit
tiistai 23. tammikuuta 2018
tiistai 17. marraskuuta 2015
Baumgarten: Metaphysics – Definition of existence
One of the most
perplexing parts of Wolff's ontology is his notion of determination –
something that can be affirmed of a thing. Are these determinations
subjective or objective? The definitions appear to support the former
reading, but the way Wolff actually uses these determinations to
define possible things seems to support the latter reading.
Furthermore, it is unclear whether these determinations should be
universals or abstract particulars, i.e. tropes. The most faithful
reading would perhaps be to deny that determinations are either,
since both universals and particulars are defined through the
determinations. Still, they seem more like universals, since unlike
with particulars, they could be joined with other determinations.
Whatever these
determinations are, Baumgarten accepts the notion, although he defines
it in a somewhat different manner. Something is determinate,
Baumgarten says, when it has been posited as A or not-A. The term
”posited” might seem rather strange, and indeed it is so – it
is not quite clear whether Baumgarten wants to say that something is
affirmed as A or not-A or whether it merely is
A or not-A or perhaps both. Still, what is posited in something
determinate is then a determination. If the posited determination is
positive, it is a reality, otherwise it is negation. Since it seems
objectively quite hard to say, which predicates should be called
positive and which negative, the division appears rather arbitrary –
yet, it should not be just subjective, since Baumgarten clearly
distinguishes cases, in which e.g. seemingly positive determinations
are actually negative.
Baumgarten's
manner of distinguishing various determinations appears familiar from
Wolffian ontology. Determinations can belong to a thing either as the
thing is in itself – then it a question of absolute or internal
determinations – or then as the thing is with respect to other
thing – then it is a question of relations or external
determinations. The internal determinations of a thing are either
ground for all other internal determinations – then they are
essentials, sum of which forms an essence – while other internal
determinations are affections. Affections are then either wholly
grounded in essentials – then they are attributes – or not –
then they are modes.
Now,
Baumgarten notes that a possible thing must be something that can be
regarded in itself or without any relations to other things – that
is, a possibility must be something with at least a minimal identity,
by which to regonise it. This is quite a remarkable suggestion that
is not included, at least explicitly,
in Wolff's ontology. The important consequence of this suggestion, on
the other hand, is something that we find from Wolff. If something is
possible, it must have some internal determinations, because without
them we could not speak about anything, and
since these determinations must be grounded on something, the
possible thing must have an essence. In other words, all possible
things should have an essence.
Clearly
a thing with some essence could also be merely possible, since e.g.
centaurs do have an essence without existing – this is something
Wolff agrees upon. A natural question then is what makes something
possible into something actual or existent. Wolff's answer is,
briefly put, that it ultimately has something to do with God's
decision to create just this particular world, but that it also lies
beyond complete understanding of human beings. In this matter,
Baumgarten deviates considerably from Wolffian example, although
almost no one has recognised it.
Baumgarten
almost equates the essence of a possible thing with its possibility.
What about the rest of the internal determinations of a thing,
especially its modes, which are not determined by mere essence?
Simple, they are part of existence. More determinately, it is the sum
of all the internal determinations that supposedly forms the
existence of a thing. In other words, while all actual things clearly
cannot have any more determinations and are in that sense complete,
all possible things should also be in some measure incomplete or
indeterminate.
Baumgarten's
theory is remarkably curious, although even more curious is that
Wolff has been considered to endorse this theory, at least
implicitly. True, Wolff says that actual things are completely
determinate, but he never affirms that all completely determinate
things would be actual. In fact, Wolff identifies complete
determination with another ontological notion, or individuality. As
Wolff, for instance, accepts the existence of haecceitas, which might
be described as an analogy of essence in individuals, it seems quite unreasonable to
suppose that Wolff would have thought all individuals are actual.
Baumgarten, on the
other hand, makes this bold move and declares all individuals to be
existent, thus denying the possibility of merely possible
individuals. One explanation might be that he has been led astray by
the notion of positing in his definition of determinations. True, we
human beings can posit some thing to be completely determinate, only
if we can experience it and thus know that it exists. Yet, this does
not mean that God with his infinite capacity of thinking –
something which Baumgarten himself should believe in – could not
think of a completely determinate individual, which still would not
exist. It is then Baumgarten who has fallen for the old trick of
confusing capacities of human understanding with the capacities of
divine understanding – something, of which Kant was to later accuse
his rationalist predecessors.
lauantai 12. huhtikuuta 2014
Fully determined individuals
In a couples of posts ago, I compared
Wolffian things or possibilities with coherent lists of predicates or
determinations, as Wolff calls them. Now, he also mentions the
possibility that such a thing would be fully or in every possible
manner determined. Wolff doesn't really explain what this means, but
one might put it like this. Think the aforementioned lists as answers
to multiple choice questionnaires, in which one can, with each
question, choose one among many possibilities or leave the question
unanswered. Clearly, there is the distinct possibility that all the
questions of the questionnaire would be answered – then the answers
would describe a fully determined entity.
This simile undoubtedly hinges on the
assumption that all possible predicates in such lists could be
ordered in the form of such a questionnaire – in effect, a space of
possible predicates a thing can fulfill. Wolff himself just
innocently accepts this possibility, and I shall also not pursue the
question whether the assumption is as innocuous as it looks. Indeed,
there is no need, as the notion of fully determinate list of
predicates could be characterised even without the notion of such a
questionnaire. Just think what adding a new predicate to a fully
determined list would do: either it would contradict some combination
of the other predicates in the list or then be deducible from such a
combination. One need then only to take this characteristic as the
defining feature of a fully determined thing.
Being fully determined is then what
defines an individual thing, according to Wolff. In addition, being
fully determined is also a necessary characteristic of all actual
things, and indeed, one rarely sees e.g. otherwise featureless birds
flying around. In effect, Wolff is here showing his nominalist leanings. Then again, Wolff clearly is not committed to the idea that
full determination would define actuality, as some of his successors
were to do. This leaves open the possibility of merely possible
individuals that are not actualised (say, a person just like me,
except with red hair).
Now, Wolff notes that one need not list
all the predicates of an individual to define him. Just think of a
triangle with all angles equal – we do not need to tell anymore
that its sides are also equal, because this follows from the equality
of its angles. Clearly then we could have a minimal set of predicates
defining an individual entity – indeed, we could probably have many
of them or it wouldn't be a unique set or list (for instance, in case
of the triangle, the implication goes both ways, so we could as well
begin with the equality of the sides). Such a minimal list would then
define what could be called an individual essence, but which Wolff
prefers to call by the medieval name haecceitas.
Just as we can distinguish those
questionnaires that are fully completed, we can also talk about
incomplete questionnaires or lists of predicates that can still be
consistently augmented by truly new predicates. If a complete
determination defined individuals, incomplete determination then
defines genera and species. Wolff apparently doesn't use the modern
idea of genera and species as sets of individuals or extensions of
certain concepts. Instead, Wolffian genera might be called
”incomplete individuals”: we add some determinations to our
would-be individual, but leave it otherwise hazy and vague. Of
course, such a vague entity cannot really exist, just like there's no
generic triangle, but it might be actualised in various individuals
that have the exact properties this vague object is supposed to have.
We might say the generic entities are fictional, but they are useful
for bringing out the various groupings of individuals. Such a vague
entity then has some essence, just like individual had its
haecceitas: essence is similarly a minimal list of predicates for such
a generic entity.
The genera and species or universals
form then a hierarchy, arranged according to their level of
determination. The ultimate bottom of this hierarchy is formed
by individuals, the only truly actual aspect of the hierarchy. Furthermore, Wolff suggests that in well-planned
hierarchy the genera correspond not just with some accidental
combinations of characteristics, but reveal how the things are
produced. In other words, individuals corresponding to same generic
entity should have a similar genesis, just like two humans share some
points as to how they have been generated. Furthermore, belonging to
a certain genus should determine not just some determinate
characteristics of a thing, but also all the possible manners how the
thing can be modified.
So much for individuals, next time we
shall consider Wolff's notion of necessity.
maanantai 11. helmikuuta 2013
Christian Wolff: Remarks on Reasonable thoughts on God, the world and the human soul, also on all things in general - Fragments of ontology
It's hard to do commentary on another
commentary – you are twice removed from the real meat of the
problematic, and because the commentary itself has no clear
organisation, there usually is no guiding thread to connect the
various points. Thus, after reading the chapter on ontology I was
left with mere crumbs that by themselves would not have the required
length of a blog post. Still, I didn't want to make the
time spend with Wolff's commentary go to waste, so I present some of
these crumbs in a fragmentary fashion.
***
One key point in the atheism dispute
has been the notion of modalities: if Wolff says that events in the
world are hypothetically necessary, doesn't this make his theory
Spinozistic? Wolff's consideration of modalities here reveals his own
belief – Wolff has to define modalities in this manner to avoid
Spinoza's fatalism. That is, Spinoza could say only that possibility
means something that has existed, will exist or does exist, which
would make all possibilities become actual someday. Wolff's
definition of possibility as non-contradictoriness allows the
extension of possibility to be larger than the extension of past,
present and future actuality. Thus, the only truly necessary thing
for Wolff is God, who has no external cause, while other things
require some previous cause for their actualisation. Interestingly,
the tide of philosophy was to go backwards. What is true sense of
possibility and necessity for Wolff, will be disparaged by Kant as a
mere formal notion of modalities, while the mere hypothetical
necessity and possibility in a world of Wolff are raised to the
status of real or ontologically substantial modalities by Kant.
***
Connected with the Wolffian
theory of modalities is his notion of essences, which he clarifies in
his commentary through a helpful simile: if I want to determine what
a triangle is like, I need to only determine its essence, that is,
two of its sides and the angle between them, because the rest of the
triangle is determined through these measures. Unexpectedly, this
very same example occurs in Hegel, when he explains how the sensuous
side of a thing (say, a triangle) contains lot of surplus material
that could be summarized through a lot simpler structure (in
this case, through the three quantities). I suspect that Hegel didn't
bother to read that much Wolff, so the coincidence is even more
surprising.
***
Wolff's nominalism is a
feature I did not emphasize the first time around: he explicitly says
that universals or genera and species are mere summaries for
similarities between things (A and B are both ostriches because they
resemble one another and all the other ostriches . An interesting
question is then how the similarity is to be defined, and in general,
how things are distinguished from one another. Now, in some places
Wolff appears to admit at least the possibility or conceivability
that two spatially separated individuals of the same species might be
identical in every other respect, thus going against Leibnizian
principle of the identity of indiscernibles. Then again, Wolff also
subscribes to the definition of individuals as fully determinate in
comparison to incompletely determined universals – we noted in case
of Thümmig that this definition appears to naturally lead to the Leibnizian
principle, because two distinct individuals couldn't on account of
this definition be completely similar, because they would then belong
to a genus defined by all their characteristics – contradiction,
because this genus would then be a completely determinate universal.
One possible solution might be that the complete determination of
individuals would not consist of mere qualities, but also of
quantitative and spatial determinations. Indeed, Wolff says
ambiguously that individuals are determined by what we can perceive
in them, which might include also their position in space.
***
Next time it's on to
psychology!
sunnuntai 7. lokakuuta 2012
Ludwig Philipp Thümmig: Institutions of the Wolffian philosophy provided for the use of academics - Fully determinate individuals
The difference of individuals and
universal properties has been recognized at least since the time of
Aristotle. Indeed, it is obvious that the universal genus of horse is
not an individual horse, although on some reading Plato had treated
the genus just as one individual among others. Despite the
familiarity of the distinction, it is quite hard to say what exactly
differentiates universals from individuals.
Now, Thümmig suggests the rather
curious definition that individuals are fully determinate in every
way, while universals are still further determinable. The idea behind
the strange definition is actually rather simple. Take some general
class of things, such as vertebrates. Now, if we know that an animal
is a vertebrate, we know something of it – at least that it has a
vertebra. Still, many other characteristics of the said animal are
completely undetermined by its being a vertebrate, for instance,
whether it flies or not. Universal vertebrate is thus determined
through this collection of properties shared by all vertebrates. This collection does still not determine any concrete individual,
because a particular vertebrate has still some characteristics not
included in the collection.
Similarly, all concrete individuals
must be completely determined in respect of all possible characteristics (presumably there's an infinity of such possible characteristics). In other words, we cannot have an
individual thing that would neither have a certain characteristic nor not
have it: the individual must be determinately one or the other. Furthermore, nothing but a completed determination of possible characteristics could individuate a particular thing. One might object that it could still be possible that an
individual is identifiable through some incomplete list of
characteristics – for instance, George Washington can be plucked
out from the rest of the humanity by him being the first president of
United States, even if we didn't knew what he was called. But the
objection forgets that in Wolffian philosophy we are allowed to look
at other possible worlds. Thus, there could be another possible world
where the first president of United States was a man called Thomas
Jefferson, and the given description would not distinguish the two
possible first presidents. Note that while an individual is
determinate in all aspects, we might not be able to determine all its aspects.
Some universals and no individuals are
then clearly indeterminate in some respect, but Thümmig's definition suggests also
that all completely determinate things are individuals, but never universals.
This is a far more uncertain proposition. Suppose for instance that
we would know a particular rock and all its characteristics
completely. Now, if we could then copy the rock and its exact
characteristics, we would have two different individuals with the
exactly same characteristics. In fact, the list of these
characteristics would be completely determined - this was the presupposition - but it would also
define a universal class containing several individuals (the two rocks).
Thümmig's definition thus clearly
presupposes the idea that no two individuals could have a matching
set of characteristics. This principle of the identity of indiscernibles originates actually from Leibniz, who according to a story once
challenged courtiers to look for two exactly similar leaves just to
prove the principle. Indeed, the principle might well be empirically
sound, but as the thought experiment shows, it shouldn't be really
accepted as an incontestable axiom of pure reason – and certainly
it should not be hidden within a definition. Still, Thümmig's
mistake is small when compared to what Baumgarten later did with the
same notions – more on this later.
Next time we shall look on animal
psychology.
Tilaa:
Blogitekstit (Atom)