Whether it was called something (Etwas) or thing (Ding), which Crusius prefers, ontologies of the time often began from a concept opposite to nothing. By this thing that is not nothing, Crusius explains, we can mean anything whatsoever that can be thought of. Yet, he continues, we can also distinguish in the class of things that can be thought those which we can only think (merely possible things) and those that are or exist also outside our thought (actual things or things in a more proper sense).
Crusius follows Hoffman in trying to find criteria for recognising what is possible and what is not and finding ultimately three criteria, only one of which is absolutely certain. The basic sign of something being a possible thing, Crusius insists, is whether someone can think it: possibility is thus equated with an ideal comprehensibility. Since no one could think as true such things that contradict themselves or known truths, we must assume that such contradictions are a sign of an impossible thing.
The principle of non-contradiction, Crusius says, is a demand that all possible things should fulfill. Then again, he adds, all possible things need not be comprehensible to us humans: a point that Hoffman made before Crusius. The idea behind this rejection is that a more perfect mind (such as God) might be able to comprehend something we cannot. Thus, if such a perfect and undeceiving person tells us to believe some apparent absurdity (say, about three persons in one divinity), then we should believe him. Crusius points out two other cases where we should believe such absurdities to be true or at least possible. Firstly, since the law of non-contradiction is the highest criteria of possibility, we must believe a seeming absurdity, if denying it would create contradictions. Secondly, if we are obligated to assume something incomprehensible in order to perfect ourselves, then we should surely accept these incomprehensibilities as true or at least possible. If none of these conditions holds and nothing else speaks to the contrary, then we should think it impossible to separate what we cannot think as separated and to combine what we cannot think as combined. These two principles complete Crusius’ criteria of possibility.
Moving on to Crusius’ criterion for recognising what is actual we might wonder whether he is actually talking about necessity: if we try to deny something actual, we immediately or mediately assume something we cannot think as true, that is, something impossible. The perplexity might go away, if we assume that, just like possibility was defined in relation to the perfect divine mind, so perhaps actuality is also here defined in relation to God. After all, God knows perfectly what there is, so if he assumes something to be non-existent, which actually is, he would land in contradiction.
Humans are not divine, so we have only a limited connection to what is actual. The human criteria of actuality, Crusius says, are always linked to sensation, which Crusius defines as a state where we are immediately forced to assume something without any further proof and which will not be revealed as imagination or dream when compared with other sensations. Indeed, without sensation we could not know that anything exists outside our own thoughts. Even our own existence we become aware of not through our thinking, like Descartes insisted, but through our internal sensation, Crusius concludes.
Having thus delineated the realm of possible and actual things, as far as we humans can know them, Crusius defines some further concepts that he will study in more detail later. For instance, when we think of a thing, whether possible or actual, we think it as distinct from other things. In other words, we think what this thing is as different from all others or we think about its (metaphysical) essence. This essence might be divided into various aspects, which help to distinguish the thing in question from some things, but not from others, just as redness serves to distinguish rose from green things, but not from tomatoes. Such aspects Crusius calls properties or qualities. Since what a thing is is a question different from whether a thing is, existence is still something different from essence and its constituent properties: essence and properties are something we can think of, existence is something beyond thought.
Näytetään tekstit, joissa on tunniste actuality. Näytä kaikki tekstit
Näytetään tekstit, joissa on tunniste actuality. Näytä kaikki tekstit
keskiviikko 6. huhtikuuta 2022
tiistai 17. marraskuuta 2015
Baumgarten: Metaphysics – Definition of existence
One of the most
perplexing parts of Wolff's ontology is his notion of determination –
something that can be affirmed of a thing. Are these determinations
subjective or objective? The definitions appear to support the former
reading, but the way Wolff actually uses these determinations to
define possible things seems to support the latter reading.
Furthermore, it is unclear whether these determinations should be
universals or abstract particulars, i.e. tropes. The most faithful
reading would perhaps be to deny that determinations are either,
since both universals and particulars are defined through the
determinations. Still, they seem more like universals, since unlike
with particulars, they could be joined with other determinations.
Whatever these
determinations are, Baumgarten accepts the notion, although he defines
it in a somewhat different manner. Something is determinate,
Baumgarten says, when it has been posited as A or not-A. The term
”posited” might seem rather strange, and indeed it is so – it
is not quite clear whether Baumgarten wants to say that something is
affirmed as A or not-A or whether it merely is
A or not-A or perhaps both. Still, what is posited in something
determinate is then a determination. If the posited determination is
positive, it is a reality, otherwise it is negation. Since it seems
objectively quite hard to say, which predicates should be called
positive and which negative, the division appears rather arbitrary –
yet, it should not be just subjective, since Baumgarten clearly
distinguishes cases, in which e.g. seemingly positive determinations
are actually negative.
Baumgarten's
manner of distinguishing various determinations appears familiar from
Wolffian ontology. Determinations can belong to a thing either as the
thing is in itself – then it a question of absolute or internal
determinations – or then as the thing is with respect to other
thing – then it is a question of relations or external
determinations. The internal determinations of a thing are either
ground for all other internal determinations – then they are
essentials, sum of which forms an essence – while other internal
determinations are affections. Affections are then either wholly
grounded in essentials – then they are attributes – or not –
then they are modes.
Now,
Baumgarten notes that a possible thing must be something that can be
regarded in itself or without any relations to other things – that
is, a possibility must be something with at least a minimal identity,
by which to regonise it. This is quite a remarkable suggestion that
is not included, at least explicitly,
in Wolff's ontology. The important consequence of this suggestion, on
the other hand, is something that we find from Wolff. If something is
possible, it must have some internal determinations, because without
them we could not speak about anything, and
since these determinations must be grounded on something, the
possible thing must have an essence. In other words, all possible
things should have an essence.
Clearly
a thing with some essence could also be merely possible, since e.g.
centaurs do have an essence without existing – this is something
Wolff agrees upon. A natural question then is what makes something
possible into something actual or existent. Wolff's answer is,
briefly put, that it ultimately has something to do with God's
decision to create just this particular world, but that it also lies
beyond complete understanding of human beings. In this matter,
Baumgarten deviates considerably from Wolffian example, although
almost no one has recognised it.
Baumgarten
almost equates the essence of a possible thing with its possibility.
What about the rest of the internal determinations of a thing,
especially its modes, which are not determined by mere essence?
Simple, they are part of existence. More determinately, it is the sum
of all the internal determinations that supposedly forms the
existence of a thing. In other words, while all actual things clearly
cannot have any more determinations and are in that sense complete,
all possible things should also be in some measure incomplete or
indeterminate.
Baumgarten's
theory is remarkably curious, although even more curious is that
Wolff has been considered to endorse this theory, at least
implicitly. True, Wolff says that actual things are completely
determinate, but he never affirms that all completely determinate
things would be actual. In fact, Wolff identifies complete
determination with another ontological notion, or individuality. As
Wolff, for instance, accepts the existence of haecceitas, which might
be described as an analogy of essence in individuals, it seems quite unreasonable to
suppose that Wolff would have thought all individuals are actual.
Baumgarten, on the
other hand, makes this bold move and declares all individuals to be
existent, thus denying the possibility of merely possible
individuals. One explanation might be that he has been led astray by
the notion of positing in his definition of determinations. True, we
human beings can posit some thing to be completely determinate, only
if we can experience it and thus know that it exists. Yet, this does
not mean that God with his infinite capacity of thinking –
something which Baumgarten himself should believe in – could not
think of a completely determinate individual, which still would not
exist. It is then Baumgarten who has fallen for the old trick of
confusing capacities of human understanding with the capacities of
divine understanding – something, of which Kant was to later accuse
his rationalist predecessors.
tiistai 1. huhtikuuta 2014
Ocean of essences
When blogging about Wolff's German
metaphysics, I described his idea of modalities through an analogy of
an ocean warmed by sun: possibilities swam like drops of water within
the ocean, and occasionally heat of the sun made one such drop rise
to the air of actuality. In this text I am going to dive deeper to
that ocean and describe in more detail its denizens or possibilities.
But before going into possibilities, I must begin with
impossibilities.
As should be familiar, Wolff defines
impossibility through the notion of contradiction: what is
contradictory cannot exist and vice versa. Impossibility is then also
identified with what in previous text was called nothing. Possibility
is defined as contradictory of impossibility, that is,
possibility is something or what is not contradictory.
Now the definition above gives a rather
good recipe for recognizing an impossibility – if a contradiction
pops up, it cannot be. On the contrary, it is still uncertain how one
can recognize something as possible, because it is more difficult to
know when something is without contradiction. Wolff himself mentions
that we can have a priori proofs that something is possible, which
might sound rather preposterous. Yet, one must remember that by a
priori Wolff actually means all sorts of demonstrations, which can
have empirical premisses. Indeed, Wolff appears to accept only
actuality of something as an undemonstrated justification of it's
possibility. Thus, we can learn that something is possible only by
showing where to find or how to make it actual or by demonstrating it
from the actual existence of something else.
What then are the possibilities and
impossibilities according to Wolff? Simply put, we can think of them
as lists of characteristics. Picture a huge paper full of
descriptions like ”triangular”, ”round”, ”square”,
”humanoid”, ”animal”, ”mushroom”, ”pouty”,
”frivolous”, ”intelligent”, ”rioting” and infinitely many
others. Circle some of these characteristics or determinations: if
the set of characteristics is such that all its members can belong to
a single entity, the set describes a possibility, if not, an
impossibility. Note that we then have more and less detailed lists –
a pair ”pyramid” and ”red” can be made more detailed by the
inclusion of characteristic ”coppery”.
Now, if you are aiming at possible
result, obviously circling some determinations will make it necessary
to circle also other determinations. For instance, if we accept
Euclidean geometry without further ado – and they did this back at
Wolff's time – circling description ”triangular” forces us also
to circle the description ”sum of angles equals two right angles”.
The first characteristic, as it were, determines the second, or using
terminology of the previous text, thing having this characteristic is
a sufficient reason for it having that characteristic.
Let us now assume that we have chosen a
set of characteristics, which are meant to define certain possible
thing. This set forms then the essence of the supposed possibility
(say, triangularity forms the essence of triangles). Clearly,
changing any characteristics that is part of the essence would change
the possibility (e.g. square wouldn't be a triangle anymore). In this
sense essence is always constant for the possibility it corresponds
to. This doesn't mean that e.g. triangular pieces of matter could not turn to square piece of matter: then this piece of matter just
wouldn't correspond to the essence of triangularity anymore. In
effect, when we speak of an essence of a thing, we must assume some
viewpoint from which to decide what is essential and what not for the
thing in question.
Note that just putting together
characteristics does not produce an essence, because such a list does
not necessarily refer to any possibility. What one must do is also to
show the possibility of this set of characteristics. We have just
seen that it is only through actuality that such a proof can be
effected. In fact, we need what Wolff has called a real definition,
that is, an account of how the thing to be defined can be generated.
Now, when we have determined an
essence, clearly also those characteristics determined by the essence
will be constant – they cannot change, unless the essence changes.
Such determined constant characteristics Wolff calls attributes (note
that it might be equally contextual what to takes as essence and what
as attribute). Some of these attributes are shared by things with
other essences – these Wolff calls common attributes – while
others are proper only for the things with that essence.
While essences and attributes are
constant for thing of a certain sort, there are characteristics that
are not, that is, modes. Thus, triangle could continue being
triangle, even if its colour would change. Clearly such a distinction
between essential and non-essential characteristics depends on the
perspective – while colour is not essential to a triangle, it would
be to a green triangle. Furthermore, the modes are not completely
separate from essential characteristics and attributes. In fact, some
sets of possible modes (say, a set of possible colours of a triangle)
clearly form an attribute of the thing in question (it is not
necessary that a triangle has any particular colour, but it must
definitely have some colour).
In addition to essential
characteristics, attributes and modes, things also have relations to
one another. A peculiar notion of Wolff, derived probably from
Leibniz, is the conviction that all relations could be reduced to
modes. In effect, this means that one need not discuss other things
when dealing with one thing. Thus, while essential characteristics
and attributes of a thing can be explained through one another, its
modes can be grounded on its other modes, current or past – that
is, all causal processes can be regarded as involving only one object
at a time.
Wolffian sea of possibilities is then
filled with such groupings of characteristics. Characteristics of one
thing cannot clash with one another, or otherwise there wouldn't be
any such thing. Yet, just by being a possibility, the thing still
isn't actual – one must still add something to make it actual. Kant
was later to criticize Wolff, because no addition of a new
characteristic could make possibility into actuality. Yet, here Kant
is clearly too harsh for Wolff, who knew that mere addition of
characteristic would no difference, but ”something else” is
required – what this something else, is purposefully left unsaid by
Wolff at this point of discussion, although later on it becomes
evident that it is the spark of God that makes everything actual.
So much for possibilities, next time I shall look at what Wolff has to say about identity.
Tilaa:
Blogitekstit (Atom)