The purpose of state or republic, according to Crusius, is to guarantee common good of its citizens, and prudence in affairs of state means finding the best means for this common good. Crusius notes that no one constitution is the only possible means for common good - all three simple constitutions (monarchy, aristocracy and democracy) and their various combinations could work. Following tradition beginning from Aristotle, Crusius remarks that all of these constitutions could also be corrupted, if the regents of the state cared only for themselves and their own class (e.g. the three simple constitutions could be corrupted into tyrannies, oligarchies and ochlocracies). This corruption or illness of republic, Crusius clarifies, is not to be confused with mere irregularity of republic, where its constitution does not wholly serve the common good - irregularity does not yet give subjects right to overthrow their regents nor does it give other republics a right to meddle in its affairs.
In practice, Crusius advises that constitution of a republic should somehow restrict the power of regent. At least during the crucial time, when a new regent is required, either citizens should have a say in choosing the new government of the republic or this should be precisely determined by the constitution, so that the common good would not be too dependent on whims of an arbitrary individual. Indeed, the constitution should allow for strengthening and weakening the power of the regent, as the situation demanded.
In monarchy, Crusius specifies, regularity of the state demands that the power of the monarch is restricted by immutable laws, and even better, by an independent council or collegium, because individual rulers can easily become vicious. Still, Crusius adds, these restrictions shouldn’t get in the way of swift decisions, if common good required them. Furthermore, Crusius suggests that monarchies should be hereditary, because this would allow educating future monarchs to their position.
In addition, hereditary monarchies fall more rarely in civil wars, Crusius believes. In fact, he considers civil war so great a danger that he counsels making hereditary lines definite. Crusius advises particularly against monarchies with several monarchs, because at worst this encourages civil wars and at best it still weakens the republic.
Crusius has not as much to say about aristocracies and democracies. He notes that aristocracies should not be hereditary, because that could prevent best people becoming regents. Furthermore, Crusius thinks that rules stating how an aristocratic counsel comes to a decision should be clear, so that there would be no ambiguity about the decision making process. Of democracies Crusius really has nothing to say beyond noting that it requires a completely civilised nation.
In addition to choosing a constitution, Crusius continues, prudence in affairs of state concerns also the day-to-day decisions of a republic. Individual republics have their own particular circumstances requiring particular decisions, but Crusius notes that some general rules can be justified already by the general nature of republics.
Crusius begins by noting that good and prudent government has three goals, none of which should be ignored nor emphasised over others. First goal is to secure the position of regent and apply his powers most efficiently. Crucius remarks that writers like Machiavelli had focused on this goal, forgetting that the good of the regent was intricately connected with the good of the citizens, the second goal of prudent government. This second goal was overemphasised, Crusius says, by republican writers, who had forgotten that a republic still required an efficient regent. Finally, Crucius picks as the third goal the status of republic among other republic. Just like with other goals, he notes that some politicians focused too much on this particular goal, forgetting that external glory of state is based on its internal happiness.
Crusius states that prudence in affairs of state uses the very same capacities as prudence in private affairs, although it applies these capacities in different matters, which it then ought to be informed of. Specifically prudent governor should know the geographical characteristics of the land and the citizens, the political constitution of the whole republic and various communities within it, economic state of the republic, and finally, interests and goals of neighbouring republics.
Crusius emphasises the role of religion as the basis of security of republics. In addition to religion, sciences, arts and freedom of thinking should be protected, because they serve as means for securing all the goals of human life and make republics respected. Despite the lip service to freedom of thinking, Crusius is not willing to tolerate ideas working against the security of state, such as, he insists, atheism.
Crusius advises regents to be careful in choosing their officials and to prefer intelligent and virtuous people over those of high birth. Still, he also suggests that regents should not replace their own intelligence with the intelligence of their officials and that they should closely control the doings of those officials, because they work in the name of the regent. Crusius insists that officials should always follow direct commands of regent, to make the republic secure, while laws, according to Crucius, can be broken, if it is prudent to do so. Indeed, Crusius suggests, good example of regent guides subjects better than any laws.
Crusius speaks for strict regulation of state spendings - republic should always have some reserve finances, in case money is required for emergencies. Money shouldn’t particularly be given freely to subjects, Crusius argues, because they wouldn’t respect what they haven’t worked for, and they particularly shouldn’t have the right to press their own coinage. Instead, subjects should be taxed heavily, Crusius says, since no citizen should have means to live by oneself, but be in various ways dependent on other citizens. Indeed, a person providing sustenance to others should be congratulated, Crusius suggests, because they help to realise one goal of republic. To make taxation fair, Crusius notes, richer individuals should pay the most. Generally, he insists that money should be directed to move from owner to another from time to time, since in this manner it helps the state and the subjects more than if it remained stagnant. Thus, if some goods in land were still ownerless, they could be taken as regent’s property, so that they could be used for everyone’s benefit.
Crusius has not very much to say about legislation, beyond the general fact that laws should be applicable to different subjects. Furthermore, Crusius emphasises that laws should definite, so that there can be no room for misinterpretation, whether it is accidental or purposeful. Against another sort of fraud is directed Crusius’ advise that regents should be careful that religious communities won’t meddle into civil life of their members, since this is often a way to deceive lower classes.
When it comes to foreign relations, Crusius advocates for maintaining the army in good condition, because a strong army has an important role in preventing foreign conquest and in raising the prestige of the republic, which is important for achieving its goals. In commerce, Crusius holds onto essentially mercantilist ideals: foreign imports should be restricted, because losing gold weakens the state, and if something is to be imported, it should be raw materials that are then further developed into manufactures that could be sold to other countries for more money. Crusius still does not believe that republics are only competitors of one another. Indeed, he says that just like humans require friends, countries require alliances for their own security.
Näytetään tekstit, joissa on tunniste politics. Näytä kaikki tekstit
Näytetään tekstit, joissa on tunniste politics. Näytä kaikki tekstit
sunnuntai 9. helmikuuta 2020
perjantai 13. joulukuuta 2019
Christian August Crusius: Instruction to live reasonably - Republics and nations
Until this moment, Crusius has been speaking of a state of nature, that is, a state without no government. Then again, he notes, human beings cannot remain in this state of nature, because their fallen state creates problems. Some people want to do harm to others, and a need to defend oneself leads to the formation of communities. Crusius insists that not everyone can take part in the actual decision making of a community, which requires some form of representation. Furthermore, communities require some principles to fill gaps in the law of nature and means by which to enforce natural law and contracts.
These needs generate an incentive to form republics, by which Crusius means communities in which one or more persons take care of common welfare and security, in order that natural duties and rights of moral person would be better protected. Crusius also insists that God wants republics, because they are in the current state of the world the best means for common welfare. Crusius does admit that first republics were probably dictatorships. Still, he thinks that this genesis does not lessen our obligations toward them. Furthermore, he notes that republics are not absolutely necessary, since in state of nature many things can be determined through contracts.
Crusius notes that republics have two different kinds of members - regents or rulers and subjects or citizens - both of which have their own duties and rights. Although he notes that a republic can have many regents and that even the whole nation could be a regent, most of his discussion seems to rise from the monarchic context of a single ruler.
Duty of regents is, Crusius says, to take care of the welfare of the whole republic and to use their powers only for this purpose and not to restrict individual rights further than necessary. Rights of regent, which Crusius calls rights of majesty, can either be historically determined, such as a right to hunt in certain places where others are not allowed. Still, Crusius notes, some of their rights are determined already by the very notion of regency and thus belong to natural law.
A central right of regents, in Crusius’ account, is the right to explicitly or implicitly appoint civil laws, which are meant for the best of the whole republic and which subjects are obligated to follow. Civil laws either generally say that something should be done or not done, or they assign rights to certain people and to other people a duty to respect those rights.
Crusius bases the obligation toward civil laws on a more fundamental obligation toward natural law - civil laws should be obeyed, because natural law says so. Civil laws are mostly needed where natural law leaves matters very undetermined, for instance, with questions concerning property. In addition, they can be used to bolster parts of natural law that are not accepted by everyone.
Crusius considers also the relationship of civil laws to rights and duties based on natural laws. He notes that civil laws can cancel negative natural rights, for instance, a civil law can cancel a right to hunt. Then again, Crusius adds, positive right can be cancelled only for a good reason. Crusius thinks also that a civil law can cancel those natural duties, which are indeterminate or not in itself necessary, because civil security is more important than following these duties. Then again, he emphasises, immutable natural duties cannot be denied by any civil law, because even civil law is based on such duties.
In addition to devising civil laws, Crusius says that regent is also tasked to apply natural and civil laws as the highest judge of republic. This does not mean that regent would have to sit in court all day, because they can assign officials and judges to help them in their work. Then again, regent cannot leave judicial power to the hands of ordinary citizens - thus, Crusius condemns practices such as dueling. Finally, according to Crusius, regents themselves can judged only by God, so that the security of republic can be maintained.
Crusius says that a regent has a right to punish and thus force subjects to follow laws. In extreme cases they can even kill people, as a deterrent, but Crusius advises this should not be done lightly. Still, Crusius suggests that righteous death penalty should be regarded as deriving from God’s will.
As has already been noted, Crusius wanted regents to avoid meddling into private affairs of citizens, as much as it is possible. This means also that regent should respect property of private persons, although they have a right to tax citizens during extreme times. Crusius also notes that private affairs of regent do not fall under right of majesty, in other words, regent does not have any special rights when e.g. buying or selling property.
Crusius remarks that republic might contain smaller communities. These communities fall also under the command of regent. Thus, Crusius notes, they must provide enough information of their activities to regent, in order to determine whether they won’t pose a threat to a republic. If these communities are harmless, their activities belong to the private sphere.
Crusius also considers the origin of regent’s rights. Originally, he says, majesty must be decided by pact. Such a constitutional pact can be entered freely, but Crusius admits it might also arise through force, if the alternative is even worse. This pact can be explicit - for instance, in case of elections - or implicit. Crusius considers it as a case of an implicit pact, when children continue to live in a republic that has raised them - it is not their parents that have decided the issue, but children themselves, because they enjoy the security provided by the republic.
Crusius says that rights of regent and their limits are determined by the original pact - unless regents want to turn into dictators, they should not try to overcome those limits. Crusius is of the opinion that the rights of regent can be restricted only by an explicit pact or by clear implicit conditions, such as regent’s duty to act for the benefit of the whole republic.
Crusius notes that regent has power also over churches in republic. Indeed, he insists that churches must be regulated more than other communities, because churches are large, depravations can be easily masked as religious dogmas and unruly persons often become church officials. Still, Crusius adds, regent should otherwise give churches the same rights as other communities.
Crusius has further rules about the relationship of regent and religion. Firstly, he begins, regents themselves should not make new religions and they should not make essential changes to religion. Since regents should not meddle in private affairs, they should not force anyone to convert to a religion. Particularly, they should not take children from their parents and make them part of a different religious community. Generally, Crusius says, nobody should be punished just because of their religion. Furthermore, unless the good of the republic demands so, Crusius continues, regent should not force religious community to change its characteristics.
Crusius thinks that power of regents over a religion goes somewhat further, if they follow that particular religion, because then they are obligated to aim for the best of its followers - for instance, regents would then have also judicial power in church. Crusius suggests that regents are obligated to help their religious community survive all internal conflicts. Indeed, he adds, they can even determine the rules of the religious community, if the general good so demands.
According to Crusius, regent can pick some religion as an official religion of the republic, in so far as nobody is forced to uphold it involuntarily. Crusius notes that while regent can punish people who disturb general peace, even if they do it for the sake of their conscience, this does not mean he can punish people just for having a different religion. Still, Crusius allows regents to punish external mockery of the official religion, which Crusius considers to include atheism or deism.
Crusius thinks subjects have a duty to follow civil laws and administration of majesty, thus denying all disobedience. According to Crusius, this duty is based not just on the original pact, but also on the duty of upholding security of whole community. This duty also implies, Crusius says, that despite all their faults, regents must be thought to be good, because on the public image of the regent is based the security of whole republic. Similarly, Crusius continues, subjects must think that a regent always acts according to the best interest of republic.
Crusius admit that if regents forget the duty of upholding common good, citizens are only externally obligated to follow them. He then raises the interesting question whether this external duty of obedience contradicts inner duty of citizens to follow their own conscience. His answer differs from one case to another. Firstly, he notes that when citizens are unsure what is best for the republic, they should just follow their regent. Even if the citizens would know a better course of action than what regent suggests, regent’s suggestion should be follow not be bad as such.
What then if regent’s decision would be foolish or even ethically unsound? Advise of Crusius is to avoid as much conflict as possible. He denies all active rebellion, but accepts a sort of passive resistance, where regent’s commands are not just followed. Even in this case, Crusius says, this disobedience should be done without arousing too much commotion and the citizens should accept the punishment, if their disobedience becomes public.
Since the rights of regent are based on original, explicit or implicit, pact, these rights might vanish and subjects wouldn’t then be obligated to follow their regent. Crusius warns that this could happen only if the regent had committed a great crime, since revolution always endangers public security. Furthermore, he adds that the decision to start a revolution should not rise from a single person, but from whole nation or at least from a majority of nation or from a selected group of its representatives.
While within a republic or a nation, civil laws rule in addition to natural law, when it comes to relation of nations, Crusius says, no such civil laws exist. This means, firstly, that all nations have similar right and no nation can rule or judge over another. Secondly, Crusius adds, it means that all obligations of nations must be based on either natural law or on contracts made by them. Still, the mere existence of free nations changes the natural law somewhat from that holding in a state of nature, for instance, since the existence of nations often implies the existence of entities other than individuals that can own property.
Because free nations have no further ruler above them, Crusius notes, they have a right to force their own rights, in other words, they can start just wars. Just war is no illegal revenge, Crusius clarifies, but a righteous way for a nation to uphold its rights. Still, he points out, war is always an unnatural state and should happen only at very extreme situations, after all diplomatic means have been used. Furthermore, Crusius continues, warring nations should use the least amount of violence and to end the war as soon as possible, while neutral states should not be disturbed during war. Despite these antiwar attitudes, Crusius makes one concession: raging barbarian hordes can be attacked, no matter what.
These needs generate an incentive to form republics, by which Crusius means communities in which one or more persons take care of common welfare and security, in order that natural duties and rights of moral person would be better protected. Crusius also insists that God wants republics, because they are in the current state of the world the best means for common welfare. Crusius does admit that first republics were probably dictatorships. Still, he thinks that this genesis does not lessen our obligations toward them. Furthermore, he notes that republics are not absolutely necessary, since in state of nature many things can be determined through contracts.
Crusius notes that republics have two different kinds of members - regents or rulers and subjects or citizens - both of which have their own duties and rights. Although he notes that a republic can have many regents and that even the whole nation could be a regent, most of his discussion seems to rise from the monarchic context of a single ruler.
Duty of regents is, Crusius says, to take care of the welfare of the whole republic and to use their powers only for this purpose and not to restrict individual rights further than necessary. Rights of regent, which Crusius calls rights of majesty, can either be historically determined, such as a right to hunt in certain places where others are not allowed. Still, Crusius notes, some of their rights are determined already by the very notion of regency and thus belong to natural law.
A central right of regents, in Crusius’ account, is the right to explicitly or implicitly appoint civil laws, which are meant for the best of the whole republic and which subjects are obligated to follow. Civil laws either generally say that something should be done or not done, or they assign rights to certain people and to other people a duty to respect those rights.
Crusius bases the obligation toward civil laws on a more fundamental obligation toward natural law - civil laws should be obeyed, because natural law says so. Civil laws are mostly needed where natural law leaves matters very undetermined, for instance, with questions concerning property. In addition, they can be used to bolster parts of natural law that are not accepted by everyone.
Crusius considers also the relationship of civil laws to rights and duties based on natural laws. He notes that civil laws can cancel negative natural rights, for instance, a civil law can cancel a right to hunt. Then again, Crusius adds, positive right can be cancelled only for a good reason. Crusius thinks also that a civil law can cancel those natural duties, which are indeterminate or not in itself necessary, because civil security is more important than following these duties. Then again, he emphasises, immutable natural duties cannot be denied by any civil law, because even civil law is based on such duties.
In addition to devising civil laws, Crusius says that regent is also tasked to apply natural and civil laws as the highest judge of republic. This does not mean that regent would have to sit in court all day, because they can assign officials and judges to help them in their work. Then again, regent cannot leave judicial power to the hands of ordinary citizens - thus, Crusius condemns practices such as dueling. Finally, according to Crusius, regents themselves can judged only by God, so that the security of republic can be maintained.
Crusius says that a regent has a right to punish and thus force subjects to follow laws. In extreme cases they can even kill people, as a deterrent, but Crusius advises this should not be done lightly. Still, Crusius suggests that righteous death penalty should be regarded as deriving from God’s will.
As has already been noted, Crusius wanted regents to avoid meddling into private affairs of citizens, as much as it is possible. This means also that regent should respect property of private persons, although they have a right to tax citizens during extreme times. Crusius also notes that private affairs of regent do not fall under right of majesty, in other words, regent does not have any special rights when e.g. buying or selling property.
Crusius remarks that republic might contain smaller communities. These communities fall also under the command of regent. Thus, Crusius notes, they must provide enough information of their activities to regent, in order to determine whether they won’t pose a threat to a republic. If these communities are harmless, their activities belong to the private sphere.
Crusius also considers the origin of regent’s rights. Originally, he says, majesty must be decided by pact. Such a constitutional pact can be entered freely, but Crusius admits it might also arise through force, if the alternative is even worse. This pact can be explicit - for instance, in case of elections - or implicit. Crusius considers it as a case of an implicit pact, when children continue to live in a republic that has raised them - it is not their parents that have decided the issue, but children themselves, because they enjoy the security provided by the republic.
Crusius says that rights of regent and their limits are determined by the original pact - unless regents want to turn into dictators, they should not try to overcome those limits. Crusius is of the opinion that the rights of regent can be restricted only by an explicit pact or by clear implicit conditions, such as regent’s duty to act for the benefit of the whole republic.
Crusius notes that regent has power also over churches in republic. Indeed, he insists that churches must be regulated more than other communities, because churches are large, depravations can be easily masked as religious dogmas and unruly persons often become church officials. Still, Crusius adds, regent should otherwise give churches the same rights as other communities.
Crusius has further rules about the relationship of regent and religion. Firstly, he begins, regents themselves should not make new religions and they should not make essential changes to religion. Since regents should not meddle in private affairs, they should not force anyone to convert to a religion. Particularly, they should not take children from their parents and make them part of a different religious community. Generally, Crusius says, nobody should be punished just because of their religion. Furthermore, unless the good of the republic demands so, Crusius continues, regent should not force religious community to change its characteristics.
Crusius thinks that power of regents over a religion goes somewhat further, if they follow that particular religion, because then they are obligated to aim for the best of its followers - for instance, regents would then have also judicial power in church. Crusius suggests that regents are obligated to help their religious community survive all internal conflicts. Indeed, he adds, they can even determine the rules of the religious community, if the general good so demands.
According to Crusius, regent can pick some religion as an official religion of the republic, in so far as nobody is forced to uphold it involuntarily. Crusius notes that while regent can punish people who disturb general peace, even if they do it for the sake of their conscience, this does not mean he can punish people just for having a different religion. Still, Crusius allows regents to punish external mockery of the official religion, which Crusius considers to include atheism or deism.
Crusius thinks subjects have a duty to follow civil laws and administration of majesty, thus denying all disobedience. According to Crusius, this duty is based not just on the original pact, but also on the duty of upholding security of whole community. This duty also implies, Crusius says, that despite all their faults, regents must be thought to be good, because on the public image of the regent is based the security of whole republic. Similarly, Crusius continues, subjects must think that a regent always acts according to the best interest of republic.
Crusius admit that if regents forget the duty of upholding common good, citizens are only externally obligated to follow them. He then raises the interesting question whether this external duty of obedience contradicts inner duty of citizens to follow their own conscience. His answer differs from one case to another. Firstly, he notes that when citizens are unsure what is best for the republic, they should just follow their regent. Even if the citizens would know a better course of action than what regent suggests, regent’s suggestion should be follow not be bad as such.
What then if regent’s decision would be foolish or even ethically unsound? Advise of Crusius is to avoid as much conflict as possible. He denies all active rebellion, but accepts a sort of passive resistance, where regent’s commands are not just followed. Even in this case, Crusius says, this disobedience should be done without arousing too much commotion and the citizens should accept the punishment, if their disobedience becomes public.
Since the rights of regent are based on original, explicit or implicit, pact, these rights might vanish and subjects wouldn’t then be obligated to follow their regent. Crusius warns that this could happen only if the regent had committed a great crime, since revolution always endangers public security. Furthermore, he adds that the decision to start a revolution should not rise from a single person, but from whole nation or at least from a majority of nation or from a selected group of its representatives.
While within a republic or a nation, civil laws rule in addition to natural law, when it comes to relation of nations, Crusius says, no such civil laws exist. This means, firstly, that all nations have similar right and no nation can rule or judge over another. Secondly, Crusius adds, it means that all obligations of nations must be based on either natural law or on contracts made by them. Still, the mere existence of free nations changes the natural law somewhat from that holding in a state of nature, for instance, since the existence of nations often implies the existence of entities other than individuals that can own property.
Because free nations have no further ruler above them, Crusius notes, they have a right to force their own rights, in other words, they can start just wars. Just war is no illegal revenge, Crusius clarifies, but a righteous way for a nation to uphold its rights. Still, he points out, war is always an unnatural state and should happen only at very extreme situations, after all diplomatic means have been used. Furthermore, Crusius continues, warring nations should use the least amount of violence and to end the war as soon as possible, while neutral states should not be disturbed during war. Despite these antiwar attitudes, Crusius makes one concession: raging barbarian hordes can be attacked, no matter what.
perjantai 13. maaliskuuta 2015
Gottsched: First grounds of whole worldly wisdom, second part (1734?)
As you might notice
from the question mark, I am not completely certain about the
publication year of the second part of Gottsched's Erste Gründe
der gesammten Weltweisheit. All
the external sources I've studied indicate only a publication year
for the first book, and because I've seen only later editions of the
book, I haven't had the chance to verify this from the original
source. Luckily, in the later editions Gottsched added
as a preface his own life story, in which he clearly tells that he
finished the second part in 1734. Whether the book was also published
in the same year I do not know, but it at least seems likely.
In
the same preface Gottsched also notes that his philosophical
textbooks had been accused of being mere copies of Thümmig's Latin
textbooks. Gottsched of course denies the accusation, but one must
admit that some influences especially in the ordering of different
topics appears indubitable. For instance, in the case of this second
part, concentrating on practical philosophy, Gottsched does not
follow Wolff's double division of practical philosophy into ethics
and politics, but divides first the whole practical philosophy in the
same manner as Thümmig, according to levels of generality: the books
begins with general account of practical philosophy, moves to natural
law and only at the next level introduces the distinction to ethics
and politics.
One
particular point I forgot to mention when discussing the first part
of the book was Gottsched'd definition of philosophy, which differs
interestingly from Wolffian definition: for Gottsched, philosophy is
a science for obtaining happiness. It is clear then that Gottsched
holds practical philosophy to be of primary importance in comparison
with theoretical philosophy, which merely serves as a presupposition
of practical philosophy – one must know e.g. ontological truths
about good and bad and pneumatological truths about human behaviour
to get anywhere in practical philosophy.
An
important assumption in practical philosophy is that human beings are
in some sense free, because practical philosophy is for Gottsched all
about free actions – you cannot make evaluations out of reflexes.
Freedom, on the other hand, is dependent on us understanding the
situation and choosing what to do in that situation – a person with
seriously weak understanding, such as a child, cannot then be deemed
free and therefore cannot be blamed for his actions.
Gottsched's
practical philosophy is thus rather intellectual. Even conscience is
for him, just like for Wolff, a faculty for making judgements and
involves always syllogistic reasoning: a person has a principle of
action (in such and such a situation do this), analyses the situation
(this is such an such a situation) and then just follows the
conclusion of the deduction. Gottsched also suggests that we could
use a sort of reverse reasoning out of their actions in certain
situations what their moral principles must be. He notices the
possibility of someone faking his behaviour, but has an amusing
solution: just make him drunk enough and he will soon reveal his true
colours.
Gottsched's
rules for evaluating the actions are consequentialist: a principle of
action cannot be good, if it won't lead to good consequences. He goes
even so far as to suggest that because all actions will ultimately
lead to either good or bad results, all actions are either good or
bad. It remains rather unclear how long the causal chain starting
from an action should be followed to determine its worth – if taken
to its utmost extreme of following the consequences to final end of
the world, it appears humanly impossible to say anything about the
goodness and badness of actions.
Then
again, worth of a human being cannot be seen in one action, but more
in the general disposition appearing in a number of actions.
Furthermore, even the most virtuous person might occasionally have
relapses to vicious behaviour because of human weaknesses. Highest
good for human beings is then more like a constant attempt to improve
one's behaviour and make it more and more virtuous – this is an
idea that will reoccur e.g. in writing's of Fichte.
In
a very Wolffian fashion Gottsched suggests that the ultimate
principle of action should be the demand to make everyone perfect,
oneself and others. The care for oneself leads obviously to one's
happiness, but it is more difficult to say in Wolffian case how the
care for others can be deduced from the assumption of one's own
perfection as an end. Gottsched avoids the paradox by noting that God
has bound all human beings into a republic ruled by God, which makes
it our business to care for citizens of all the universe.
Furthermore, Gottsched also points out the Wolffian answer that even
intuiting perfection makes one happy, thus making helping one's
fellow beings a reasonably prudent choice.
It
is this striving towards universal perfection that summarises the
content of the law of nature in Gottsched. This law of nature is in a
sense backed up by God, in the sense that he has decreed all the
causal laws leading from certain actions to certain consequences –
vicious action is such that leads to unhappy life, and the connection
of the two was the creation of God. Then again, all these causal
regularities exist within the world and can be read out of it through
a correct use of reason – in other words, we do not need any
supernatural revelation to know what is good and what is bad, and
even atheists could be convinced of the law of nature.
Gottdched
goes then on to further specific features of the law of nature, which
is divided, firstly, into duties belonging to all human beings, no
matter what their status (and these are classified familiarly into
duties towards God, oneself and other human beings), and secondly, to
duties pertaining to certain social roles in e.g. a household or a
commonwealth. While the law of nature with all its subduties contains
then the general principles for all actions, concrete guidance to
correct action is provided by the science of ethics and politics.
These fields of philosophical investigation tell us how to motivate
people to follow the duties implied in the law of nature.
Furthermore, they try to give suggestions how following the law of
nature becomes easier – one should e.g. educate oneself and tame
one's affects and similarly states should provide for both
intellectual and moral upbringing of its citizens. The shape of this
system has rather Wolffian air, but in small details there are
certain differences – for instance, Gottsched seems more willing
than Wolff to allow for people helping one another, e.g. with alms.
***
This is also a good
place to consider Gottsched as a philosopher in general, since I've
now read most of his important writings. He did write a book on
rhetoric and he also published a lot of of new editions on his
earlier books – especially in his book on poetry he modified the
text and added further material as times went by. And undoubtedly a
complete picture of Gottsched would have to take into account his
poetic achievement. Still, these three books are quite enough to see
what is essential particularly in his philosophy.
One can firstly
appreciate the role of Gottsched in popularising and summarising
central tenets of Wolffian philosophy, as he quite astoundingly
manages to make out of five long books (logic, metaphysics, physics,
ethics and politics) two books, which still feel complete and full
works. One must also appreciate Gottsched's willingness to not follow
Leibniz or Wolff slavishly: he adds new material from other writers
especially in the matter of natural sciences and even distances
himself from some key Leibnizian tenets, like pre-established
harmony. Still, one feels that none of this makes Gottsched a very
original thinker, but a mere compiler.
The most influential
part of Gottsched's ouvre is undoubtedly his poetic, but even here
one feels that it is more due to historical reasons of Gottsched just
doing in German-speaking world what no one had done before. The book
does have an original flair, even if much of the topics have been
borrowed from Aristotle, Horace and modern French writers. The same
moralising and rule preaching attitude that can be glimpsed in
Gottsched's work on practical philosophy shows its full sway in his
adherence to rigid rules and in his condemnation of whole genres of
poetry. No wonder then that the rising new generation of writers
didn't follow Gottsched's instructions.
But this is getting
too much ahead of the progress of times. While we now said adieu to
Gottsched, next time we will meet a rising star in German school
philosophy.
tiistai 30. lokakuuta 2012
Ludwig Philipp Thümmig: Institutions of Wolffian philosophy provided for the use of academics, part 2 (1727?)
I noticed that in my investigation of
the theoretical part of Thümmig's work I left out a crucial element,
namely, the very structure of the science in question. A quick
schematic is here:
Few words of explanation. Logic forms
its own module in Wolffian philosophy. On the one hand, logic
precedes all other sciences, because it introduces the very method
used in all sciences. On the other hand, logic is clearly based on
psychological considerations: to know how human cognition should
work, we must know something about human cognitive powers. Because
psychology is partly an empirical science, Wolffian logic, as
described by Thümmig, must also have an empirical element.
The second module in the picture
consists of metaphysics. Here the foundation of the whole lies in
ontology, of which it is difficult to say whether it is empiricist of
rational – remember the controversy about the principle of
sufficient reason. On ontology are based both cosmology and
psychology, first of which deals with the sum of all complex objects
and second of which deals with one type of simple object or soul.
Both cosmology and psychology also have empirical foundations. In
addition to the ontological theory of complex objects, cosmology
contains also the highest generalizations from physical laws, clearly
based on observations. Even more clearly, psychology contains an
empirical part, which the so-called rational psychology then tries to
explain. Furthermore, rational psychology is also partially based on
cosmology, because psychology must explain the supposed interaction
of the soul with its body, a complex object. Finally, natural
theology is based on both cosmology and psychology – for instance,
the existence of God is deduced cosmologically from the existence of
the world and the soul.
The final module of theoretical
philosophy is then structured similarly as psychology. First, there
is the so-called experimental philosophy, which contains results of
the physical observations and experiments. The physics proper offers
then a rational explanation for the content of the experimental
philosophy , just as rational psychology was supposed to explanation
of the results of empirical philosophy. Physics is also grounded on
cosmology, which defines the most general laws governing the physical
things.
If we finally move to Thümmig's vision
of the practical philosophy of Wolffian school, we may firstly note how the practical philosophy is dependent on the theoretical
philosophy – logic is used to show how human being should use their
intellectual capacities, ontology to define the concept of goodness,
psychology to show what humans are capable of and theology to
determine how humans should take God into account.
In Wolff's writings practical
philosophy was detailed in two writings, the one dealing with ethics
and the other with civil philosophy, Thümmig's scheme makes it much
clearer that the two disciplines are actually just two parts of one
discipline. Indeed, the practical philosophy forms a more definite
unity with Thümmig than theoretical philosophy:
The practical philosophy has then a
general part, on which both of its major divisions are based. The aim
of this general part is to establish natural law as the guiding
principle of all good actions – all actions must aim towards
perfection. The natural law is then divided into two different
sublaws, depending on whether the actions involve only a single human
being or whether they involve also interpersonal relations. In the
former case, the natural law determines the obligation for an
individual to perfect one's intellect, volition, body and external
state, while in the second case natural law commands members of a
community to make other members as happy as possible and the
community in general as prosperous and tranquil as possible. The
former aspect of natural law is then the foundation of moral
philosophy or ethics, which is then nothing but a system of rules for
making oneself perfect. The latter aspect, on the other hand, is the
foundation of civil philosophy or politics, which is divided into two
parts. The first part or economics deals with the prosperity of
simple communities or households, while the second or politics
proper, which is also based on economics, deals with the prosperity
of communities consisting of households, that is, republics.
Thümmig has thus made two additions to
the Wolffian practical philosophy: firstly, he has introduced the
idea of a general practical philosophy, and secondly, he has divided
the ethics and the politics into two parts, first of which
investigates the primary goal of these disciplines and the second of
which determined the practical measures for obtaining those goals.
When it comes to details, Thümmig fails to make any substantial
additions to what Wolff himself had said in his works on ethics and
politics. This leads us naturally to the question of the role Thümmig
played in the development of German philosophy. I shall endeavor to
make similar concluding remarks on every philosopher, once I get to
the last text I read from them.
The texts of Thümmig
considered thus far have had little of lasting interest. In addition
to Institutions, he has edited one collection of Wolffian articles
and authored a book on scientific curiosities and an article
defending Wolff's German metaphysics. Even the Institutions, which
has been clearly the main publication of Thümmig, has been mostly a
mere summarized translation of Wolff's works. Of course, Institutions
still was important for the Wolffian school, because it presented the
doctrine of the school for the very first time in the international
language of the time.
Furthermore, it is clear
that Wolff and at least other Wolffians took Thümmig seriously and
referred to his writings various times. Indeed, it is just to be
expected that a promising young philosopher follows for a time the
writings of his mentor closely, before breaking into some truly new
territory. Thümmig never really had the chance to break away from
the shadow of Wolff, because he died rather young in 1728.
Still, in light of Thümmig's
writings it is difficult to say whether he could have really changed
the tone of Wolffian philosophy. He does introduce novelties, but
these novelties are not so much reformations of Wolff's doctrines,
but merely additions concerning issues Wolff had not discussed –
think, for instance, of Thümmig's fascination with animal
psychology. In contrast with later Wolffians, like Baumgarten,
Thümmig is more like a person who applies a theory to new fields of
investigation, while the later Wolffians sometimes even disputed the
theory and the axioms on which it was based – not to mention Kant,
who replaced even the methods and aims of philosophy.
So much for Thümmig, next
time we shall find out the purpose of the world.
keskiviikko 30. toukokuuta 2012
Ludwig Philipp Th'ummig: Varied essays and rare arguments, collected in one volume (1727)
When we speak of a Wolffian school, it
is not just Christian Wolff himself we are thinking of, but a whole
parade of more minor figures who in some sense continued the work of
their masters. The 1720s appear to be the earliest point at which we
can speak of Wolffians as a recognizable philosophical movement. I have already discussed a dissertation of
one Wolffian, Bilfinger, that appeared 1722, and the topic of the
current post, Meletemata varii et rarioris argumenti in unum
volumen collecta, contains
dissertations and essays published during 1720s.
Although the name
does not reveal it, the continuous references to the works of the
illustrious Wolff suggest that the writers are hard core Wolffians.
Most of the contributors are quite minor names in the school and apparently did
not even publish anything after their dissertation, so I'll skip
introducing them. The only exception is the editor of the collection,
Ludvig Philip Thümmig, a faithful follower of Wolff.
What I
am mostly interested in this collection is the range of different
topics discussed, which reflects well the multifarious nature of
Wolff's philosophy. A considerable number of the essays concern
natural or mathematical sciences, which was the original research
field of Wolff and which he still continued to study even when he had
already started his famous series on reasonable thoughts on nearly
everything – even at this time Wolff published a series called
Allerhand nützliche Versuche
(All sorts of useful studies), which dealt with such important
problems as how we can weigh objects or use a thermometer. The pupils
of Wolff appear to have been interested at least of biology (there's
an essay on how to study leaves), but especially of astronomy and
”things happening up in the sky”, like propagation of light.
It is
not just physics that interested pupils of Wolff, but there are also
more philosophical essays that concern all the four Rational
thoughts we have encountered
thus far. There's a logical discourse on the necessary and contingent
concepts, which also has ontological consequences – the writer
argues how Wolffian distinction between absolute and conditional
necessity discredits Spinoza's idea that the world is necessary,
because the existence of the world is not impossible, but depends on
the free choice of God. This writing is the first sign thus far of
the looming threat of Spinozan pantheism – we have more to say on
the matter in a couple of decades.
Furthermore, the
collection contains a metaphysical study of the immortality of soul –
or more likely, it is an advertisement of the Wolffian proof, which
is based on the simplicity of the soul and the supposed impossibility
of a material basis of thinking. The only novelty in the essay
appears to be the author's idea that the life of soul consists of a
clarification of its ideas: the newborn child has only confused
ideas, but the soul of a dead person sees everything distinctly.
Despite its unoriginality, the essay shows well the appreciation of
Wolff's rational psychology in contemporary Germany. Indeed, I think
that Kant's theory of paralogisms is primarily targeted towards
Wolffian ideas.
Morality is also
topic of an essay, which analyses the notion of sincerity. A
considerable portion of the essay is dedicated to defending Wolff's
ideas of China as an atheist and still a moral nation – an issue
that will surface often in the writings of 1720s.
Wolffian politics
is not forgotten, although this essasy covers also architectural
ideas. The author follows Wolff's suggestion that the needs of a
comunnity determine what is good art. The outcome of the argument is
that the Wolffian writings on architecture fulfill this criterion of
good art perfectly.
It is
this final tendency of subjugating art to the moral upbringing of
people that will be the topic of my next post, where I'll discuss my
first piece of fiction.
Tunnisteet:
architecture,
atheism,
China,
contingency,
ethics,
immortality,
logic,
Ludwig Philipp Thümmig,
metaphysics,
necessity,
ontology,
politics,
psychology,
rational psychology,
soul,
Spinoza,
Wolffians
torstai 24. toukokuuta 2012
Christian Wolff: Reasonable thoughts on the social life of men and especially on the community - The enlightened despot
The origin of households in the
Wolffian system is the desire for intercourse, together with the
obligation to care for the possible outcome of the intercourse, that is, children. Now, Wolff suggests that household by itself cannot satisfy
all needs of a human being. At most, a life constricted to a
household can satisfy only basic needs, but this would be only animal
and not human life – the households could not provide for the
future nor would they be able to care for higher needs like science
and arts. Wolff even invokes the Hobbesian argument that a life
without a community of men would be a life of fear, because anyone
could be killed by other people.
A community or a state is then created
by households entering into a mutual contract that aims at the
general well-being of all of them – note
that it is the head of the houshold that gets to decide the loalty of
everyone in his family. Wolff obediently notes all the six classical
possibilities with the traditional names derived from Aristotle: the
good constitutions or monarchy, aristocracy and polity and their
corrupted variants or tyranny, oligarchy and democracy. Wolff then
does allow the possibility of ”polities” or republics ruled by
majority votes, although he notes that they are often hindered
by party politics. Still, the rest of the book is clearly meant for
absolute or constitutional monarchies, where the king has all or at
least majority of power in his hands. Wolff's task is to enlighten
the German despots and make their minds accessible to reforms their
states required.
Wolffian ideal of society contains some
characteristics that justify calling him an enlightenment
philosopher. For instance, Wolff encourages kings to found schools,
colleges and universities for educating people in sciences and
handicrafts, to build hospitals and apothecaries for serving the
sick and to make the cities beautiful for all senses by filling them
with works of art and by making sure that nothing stinks. Then again,
the main interest of Wolff in politics is the upholding of public
morality, which gives Wolff's suggestions a moralizing tone. Thus,
Wolff suggests that only art that teaches morals is to be accepted
and that a state should be filled with buildings for public moral
preaching. The most extreme suggestion from modern standpoint is that
all punishments should happen in public in order that potential
criminals would think twice of their immoral intentions.
The idea of places for public moral
preaching is interesting as a not so veiled attempt to promote
churches as necessary for the well-being of the state – the attempt
becomes even more apparent, when Wolff notes that belief in God is
almost a prerequisite for a moral society. True, Wolff has admitted
that morality is possible without religion. Wolff even goes so far as
to accept China as an atheist state that has one of the best
constitutions in the world – as we shall see, this admission will
be fatal to Wolff's carrieer. Still, Wolff is convinced that majority
of atheists will be scoundrels incapable of living in community with
other people.
Wolffian politics is then not so much
interested of the welfare of the people, but of their morality –
although bodily and mental welfare is, of course, part of moral
perfection in Wolffian system. Thus, it is just natural that in
Wolff's opinion laws of a state should be based on the law introduced
already in Wolff's moral writings, that is, the natural law. Wolff
does allow some changes to be made to the natural law in case when
following it would be extremely difficult. For instance, natural law
determines that a child should become independent, when she has all
the necessary skills for taking care of herself. Yet, because it is
often hard to determine the exact time when a person has become
mature in his actions, state must make a concession and determine
some fixed age at which everyone is to be considered an adult.
Natural law is for Wolff even a higher
authority than state. Usually one must obey the rulers of one's
state, but if the rulers break the natural law, people are not
committed to obeying them. Thus, if a king tries to murder someone,
the attemped victim has the right to defend herself. Yet, Wolff
advices people to resist the ruler's will only in the cases where
one's own well-being is threatened or where one is commanded to do
immoral things. Hence, if a despot threatens to kill your neighbours,
you have no obligation to help them – unless you happen to be the
soldier who is to pull the trigger.
Wolffian system of politics appears
then to have no true stopgap for tyrants and dictators. True, Wolff
does advise kings to limit their own power and become as symbolic
rulers as king of Sweden or queen of England are nowadays. Wolff even
justifies this adivce through a comparison with the universal monarch
or God, who leaves the actual government of the world to humans. Yet,
there is no guarantee that a tyrant would follow Wolff's advice.
Indeed, Wolff can only hope that religion and the fear of God would
stop kings from tyrannical behaviour – a rather poor hope when
Wolff has just congratulated God of not meddling in human affairs.
The individual states are then related
like individual persons to one another, and just like persons ideally
act like self-enclosed monads, so should states have no concern for
the international community. Positive in this isolationism is that
Wolff thinks all warfare to be evil and justifiable only as a
self-defence – although Wolff does accept also reasonable
suspicision of evil intentions as a reason for self-defence, somewhat
like American head of state before the attack to Iraq. But Wolff
appears to be blind to the invisible economic battle that his
mercantilist tendencies generate – Wolff advices states to horde as
much money as possible, which in effect make economic co-operation
impossible in international level.
So much then for Wolffian politics.
Next time I'll have something to say about the generation of Wolffian
school.
Tilaa:
Blogitekstit (Atom)