No, I haven't been reading any books on
psychiatry lately. Medicina mentis
was apparently a popular name for a philosophy book near 1700 – for
instance, such a book was published by von Tschirnhaus, the missing
link between Spinoza and Wolff. The title refers not so much to any
mental illnesses in the modern sense, but to the task of improving
one's mind and its abilities. In effect, we are threading on the same
ground as with Wolff's book on logic.
The writer of this
particular book on mental medicine was Johann Joachim Lange. Yes, you
probably have not heard of him, but he is famous as one of the most
vehement opponents of Christian Wolff, and we shall undoubtedly meet
the fellow also in the future. Lange was a follower of pietism, a
radical Christian movement that emphasised personal experience over
institutionalised church – a protest against the stagnation of
protestantism. Indeed, Lange's main occupation was theology and many
of his works concern interpretation of Biblical texts, but Medicina
mentis should be Lange's main philosophical work.
Regarding Lange's
pietist background, it is no wonder that his view of philosophy
differs radically from Wolffian view. For Wolff, as we have seen,
philosophy practically equaled science and was characterised by a
certain method, namely, deductive system based on evident axioms and
reliable experiences. Lange, on the other hand, starts from the
supposed goal of philosophy. Philosophy is love of or striving
towards wisdom, and true wisdom, says Lange, lies in being itself, or
as it can be said in Hebrew, Jehovah (”I am”). Thus, philosophy
is for Lange all about finding God.
You won't have to
read Lange to see that this idea of philosophy is in at odds with the
Wolffian notion of philosophy, which is largely neutral as to the
object of philosophy. It is thus no wonder that Lange explictly
distances himself from the idea of philosophy as worldy wisdom
(Weltweisheit) that was so important for Wolff: what is wisdom
for the world is folly, when it comes to God. Lange even coins the
term philomoria, love of foolishness, to describe this perverted or
”pseudo-ortohodox” brother of philosophy.
Lange even gives an
account of the development of both philosophy and philomoria: the
picture above is a summarised version of the latter. Nowadays
histories of philosophy don't usually begin from antediluvian age,
but Lange boldly starts from the creation itself. The tales of
philosophy and philomoria begin with the sons of Adam. Philomoria was
an invention of Cain and his offspring, who dabbled with such
frivolities like music, while the third son of Adam, Seth, and his
offspring meditated important matters. Yes, these still were the
times when Bible passed as a reliable historical source.
I shall spare my
reader Lange's further summarisation of Bible, which quickly becomes
rather repetetive. Suffice to say that Lange thinks Bible to be the
source of all important knowledge. All the mythologies of Greek and
other people are, of course, mere incomplete recollections of the
true biblical history, while all that is good in the thoughts of
Greek and later philosophers is of biblical origin. Pythagoras and
Plato evidently learned all that they knew from Jews: a suggestion,
which goes all the way to Philo, the first famous Jewish philosopher,
and which always reminds me of a devoted Hare Krishna who tried to
sell me his religion by telling that Plato learned his wisdom in
India.
Despite the
biblical origins of Greek and later philosophy, Lange has little good
to say of any particular philosopher. Especially Lange attempts to
discredit Aristotle, who in logical works introduced scholastic
erudition to philosophy, who in his theoretical philosophy suggested
that all events are caused by the movement of the celestial spheres
and whose practical philosophy is hedonism fit for Macedonian court.
The only philosophers who come clean in Lange's scheme are virtuous
Socrates and Descartes, who purged philosophy from scholasticism.
It would be really
easy to ridicule Lange, but this would go against the primary purpose
of my blog – my aim is to understand past philosophers and their
theories, not make fun of them. Indeed, Lange is not just an isolated
figure in the arena of German philosophy, but an instance of an
antirationalist, anti-enlightenment movement that later surfaces in
such fellows as Hamann and Jacobi, who were as fierce Christians as
Lange and who opposed Kant and the later German idealists, but who
also influenced them in some measure.
Indeed, German
idealism might be characterised as a combination of the two streams
of Enlightenment, the German version of which begun with Wolffe, and
antirationalism opposing Enlightenment. This characterisation is
illustrated by Hegel's tale of the battle between Enlightenment and
faith in his Phenomenology of spirit. Enlightenment, says
Hegel, is characterised by being ”a form” or a method of
investigation. Furthermore, it is a method open for everyone and thus
what the modern world is after. In fact, Wolffian ideal of philosophy
characterised through a method of axiomatic-deductive-empiricist
science fits just this description.
But as a mere
”form” Enlightenment lacks its proper content or purpose the
method is used for. Instead, the method of Enlightenment or science
can be applied to any, even the most superficial issue: good example
is Wolff making complex deductions of the question how one can change
dates between Julian, Gregorian, Hebrew, Arabic and Bablylonian
calendars. Faith, on the other hand, has just this content, that is,
it strives for the highest fulfilment possible, which Lange and other
antirationalists called God and which we might describe in a more
secular manner as the meaning of life. But faith lacks the necessary
form, that is, it merely proclaims where the fulfilment is to be
found without providing the tools by which a person could by herself
discover it.
Combining these two
strands was what Hegel thought philosophy should do, that is,
philosophy should give everyone a chance to discover what makes life
meaningful: it is thus highly valuable and still publically teachable
enterprise. But right now we are still far from seeing how Hegel
manages to do this. Instead, next time I shall be looking at more
closely how Lange describes the actual methodology of philosophy –
and we shall see that his antirationalist ideology has strikingly
rationalist roots.
Ei kommentteja:
Lähetä kommentti