Joachim Georg Darjes (1714-1791) |
Going through even
the most insignificant philosophers of a certain era might seem like
a complete waste of time – surely one would be better using one's
time by just concentrating on the most memorable and influential
figures, like Kant and Hegel. Yet, it is just by looking at these
seemingly unimportant figures that one finds, on the one hand, clear
trends and fashions, and on the other hand, unexpected breaks in
trends and surprising novelties.
Darjes' book Die
lehrende Vernunft-kunst is one of those rare works that appears
to be quite traditional, but has interesting deviations from the
current norm. On the surface, the book seems to follow quite
faithfully the trend of Wolffian textbooks on logic, with some minor
deviations. Thus, the book begins with the ontological principle of
contradiction, introduces as its consequence something called a law
of certainty (if something is A, then it is A), and finally mentions
the principle of sufficient reason as the explanation of how actuality
differs from possibility. Quite standard division of cognition into
historical, philosophical and mathematical forms comes next together
with a classification of philosophical sciences, which in its
essentials appears quite Wolffian. Chapters on philosophical style
and general need of logic show also nothing surprising.
This has all been
just the preface, and when the actual book begins, Darjes starts to
really use the mathematical style. A typical Wolffian textbook of the
time is usually presented in numbered paragraphs. Darjes uses them also, but
he also notes whether the paragraph in question is meant to be a
definition, arbitrary stipulation, statement drawn from experience,
proposition or corollary to be proved or just an additional remark.
One at once notes that many of the propositions of the book are based
on experiences, justifying Hegel's often made complaint that logic of
his time was just a bunch of empirical statements. Of course, because
the logic is meant to be a study of human faculties of thought, it is
just understandable that introspective evidence on these faculties is
required.
It is with Darjes'
account of mental faculties that we find the true novelties. The
description of senses, imagination, memory and reflection are
sufficiently similar to Wolffian empirical psychology, although Darjes' suggestion that all sensations
are produced by actual objects seems a bit naive. The truly
surprising statement comes with the study of understanding and
concepts, which Darjes clearly defines as representations of
universals. Thus, just by stipulating, it seems, Darjes has denied
the existence of individual concepts. This makes a difference in
classification of concepts. While Wolff had spoken of a formal
difference between concepts (their differing degree of clarity) and
their material difference (whether they denote individuals or
universals), Darjes can speak only of their formal differences. But
the differences go even further. For Wolff, understanding was merely
a faculty for analysing and breaking apart our representations,
whether they be individual or universal, and thus in a perfectly
Lockean fashion just a further development of our perceptive
faculties. Darjes, on the contrary, redefines understanding as a
faculty of generalisations. In effect, Darjes is restricting the area
of understanding, but so also clarifying its role – understanding
is now clearly distinguished from senses and imagination, which might
be seen as a step toward the Kantian separation of faculties.
Some differences can
be also found in Darjes' account of definition and especially the
distinction between real and nominal definitions. Wolff had stated
that for nominal definition one had to be able to distinguish the
defined from similar things, while for real definition one had to
know why the defined thing was possible – a preferred method was to
know how to generate this thing. Clearly, nominal definitions might
not be real, but also real definitions might not be nominal, because
one could generate things one couldn't properly distinguish. Darjes,
on the other hand, defines the two types of definitions through
notion of essence and essential property. Nominal definitions mean
knowing some essential property of the thing defined, that is, a
property that the thing has constantly – clearly enough for
distinguishing the thing, but most likely also too much. The real
definition is then characterised by Darjes as knowing the essence or
the ground of all these essential properties. Here, a rule for
generating this particular thing should be enough, but evidently it
should also involve knowing what the essential properties of the
thing are and being able to distinguish it – again Darjesian real
definition is far stronger than Wolffian.
I will skip Darjes'
account of language, although it shows surprising familiarity with the
medieval theory of supposition, that is, the idea that the meaning of
the word changes depending on the context of the other words. The
reason for skipping is that Darjesian classification of judgements
shows considerable movement towards the later Kantian classification
of judgments. I have already noted that the division of judgements
according to quality and quantity were already in place in Wolff'sLatin logic.
Similar classifications occur with Darjes too, although with some
nuances.
The classification
according to quantity is almost identical to one with Wolff:
judgements are either singular, particular, universal or undetermined.
The difference is that while Wolff classified singular judgements as
a type of particular judgements, Darjes notes that they could be
classified with universal judgements, because e.g. Socrates is everyone in
the class with only him as a member.
The classification
according to quality shares similar resemblance with the Wolffian
classification. Both Darjes and Wolff start by dividing all judgements
into affirmative and negative, although Darjes apparently has rather
idiosyncratic way of understanding negative judgements as attaching
”not” to the subject of the judgement. Then, while Wolff thought
infinite judgements to be a type of negative judgements, Darjes takes
them to be a type of affirmative judgements: affirmative judgement is
either finite (its predicate is positive) or infinite (its predicate
is negative). Similarly Darjes then divided negative judgements into
conditionally and simply negative judgements.
The true innovation
of Darjes lies in his third method of classifying judgements
according to their ”whatness”. This rather obscure name hides
behind it, among other things, both Kantian classifications of
relation and modality. The basic division of judgements into simple
and complex hails already from Wolff, although he understood also
hypothetical judgements as simple, while for Darjes the only simple
judgements are what Kant would later call categorical assertoric
judgements.
Darjes then divides
complex judgements into distinctly and indistinctly complex
judgements. Starting from the easier subdivision, distinctly complex
judgements are those which clearly consist of many judgements. Such
judgements either hold that some subjudgements must hold together or
deny that such subjudgements cannot hold at the same time. In the
first type, the judgement could be simple conjunction saying that two
subjudgements do happen to be true (”A is both B and C”), but it
might also just state the hypothetical that one subjudgement is a
condition of the other (”If A is B, it is C”). The second type contains then similarly judgements that state the fact that some
subjudgement holds and another not (”A is not B, but C”), while
it might also just present a disjunction of alternatives (”A is
either B or C”). This side of the classification of complex
judgements contains then two divisions from the Kantian
classification of judgements according to their relation.
Indistincly complex
judgements then contain words that somehow modify the basic sense of
the judgement. A major part of such indistincly complex judgements
are formed by what would be later called modalities, but what Darjes
names explicative judgements – words like ”possibly”,
”impossibly”, ”necessarily” and ”contingently” explicate
the relation between the subject and the predicate. Showing again his
interest in medieval philosophy, Darjes notes that unlike what
Michael Psellus said, ”truly” and ”untruly” are not similar
explicators, but more like second-order statements about the truth or
falsity of the judgements. The rest of the indistinctly complex
judgements exclude something (”only A is/ is not B”), restrict
the validity of a judgement (”in so far as p, q) or make some
comparisons (”A is more B than C”). All in all, quite a mixed
bunch, but most important is the inclusion of modalities, which has
been the first time in my reading list that they appear in a logic
book.
Like in most books
on logic at the time, I can easily skip the part on syllogisms,
because nothing significantly new comes up in that section. Then
again, this does not mean I could close the text here, because
there's still the final section on demonstration to go through. What
is interesting in this context is Darjes' account of what he calls
undeniable and deniable judgements or propositions. At first sight,
there's nothing particularly strange about Darjes' definition of
undeniable judgements – in an undeniable judgement, we can by
having a distinct representation of the subject of the judgement say
immediately that the predicate belongs to it. Well, the definition
does have some superficial resemblance to later Kantian notion of an
analytic judgement – and the feeling of resemblance is heigtened
when one finds out that Darjes thinks the principle of contradiction
suffices as a criterion of truth for undeniable judgements.
What makes Darjes'
definition distinct from later Kantian notion of analytic judgements
is his insistence that beyond definitions and tautologies judgements based on experience are also undeniable. Although this might at
first seem rather unintuitive, Darjes does have a point. Consider the
subject of an experimental judgement – this is just an individual
we happen to represent. Now, it is quite clear that a judgement based on nothing but experience merely states some characteristic that is already evident
in this representation – we see a duck and note that it seems
white. In this sense the judgement is also based on the principle of
contradiction – if the object seems white, we cannot but affirm
this.
The difference with Kant arises probably from the fact that Darjesian definition of undeniable judgements speaks of representations in general, while Kantian definitions of analytical and synthetical judgements are made in terms of concepts. Indeed, Darjesian judgements of experience are always singular - we experience only individuals - and thus their subject cannot be or refer to universal or concept.
Of course, most of
our judgements supposedly based on experiences actually overstep the
limit of individual experiences just by making generalisations out of
individual experiences (ironically, many of the supposed experiences
in Darjes book appear to do do). The account of such judgements,
Darjes tells us, should be based on probability – which apparently
should be handled on the second part of Darjes' book. Unfortunately,
I haven't been able to find this second book on ӟbende
Vernunft-lehre” or practical logic, and I cannot even say whether
Darjes ever published it.
All in all, Darjes'
book with all its small deviations and original quirks is a sign for
an end of an era. Another sign will be seen in next post, when we say
farewell to a certain opponent of Wolff.
Ei kommentteja:
Lähetä kommentti