It is regrettable
that the most talented of Wolff's opponents, Adolph Friedrich
Hoffmann, died (1741) before writing any further works, dedicated
e.g. to metaphysics. As it is, we must take as his main work a book
on logic, Vernunftlehre
darinnen
die Kennzeichen des Wahren und Falschen aus den Gesetzen des
menschlichen Verstandes hergeleitet.
Because the work represents
the best and most systematic treatment of philosophy in the whole
anti-Wolffian school, I shall take a more careful look at the various
topics it treats over the next few texts.
As
it has been noted by Beck in his seminal work on early German
philosophy, Hoffmann appropriated much of the Wolffian tone in his
works, trying to be even more systematical than the master himself.
Indeed, reading Hoffman's logic, it appears at times like Hoffman is
the more careful and ”geometric” thinker of the two, while Wolff
seems in comparison like a bumbling empiricist disguising himself
behind a semblance of deductions and definitions and
making amateur logical mistakes.
It
is not just Wolff's style of reasoning that has influenced Hoffmann,
but also his division of topics. Thus, just like any other Wolffian,
Hoffman begins by discussing philosophy in general. But before even
that, he instructs the reader about the various parts relevant to
academic discussion and particularly the various types of statements
one will find in these discourses. Here, Hoffmann clearly tries to be
more full and complete than Wolff, who satisfies himself with
recounting the basic types of statements in supposedly mathematical
treatises. Thus, Hoffmann begins by noting that some statements in
academic writings depend on mere arbitrary choice – that is, they
are stipulations assigning a contingent definition to some words or
stating that a sign like x
is meant to refer to an unknown number.
Statements
in academic works that are not stipulations are then real statements,
that is, statements meant to describe some facts not dependent on
arbitrary choices. Most of these real statements are meant to be
justified, but others cannot be, although they must still be
accepted. Such statements Hoffmann calls postulates, thus distancing
himself from Wolffian definition, in which postulate was taken as a
statement describing some basic action possible to us (for instance,
drawing a circle). Hoffman's postulates might be convenient
idealisations, if not completely true, such as the idea that parallel
lines will meet after an infinite distance. Then again, his
postulates might also be apparently convincing generalisations that
we cannot ever prove completely, such as the statement that all human
beings desire happiness.
By
allowing such postulates into an academic discourse Hoffmann appears
to be distancing his stance from the Wolffian attitude that all
statements of philosophy should be completely justified, either
through experience or through demonstration. Indeed, Wolff does
occasionally admit that some of his statements have been just likely
hypotheses, but Hoffmann makes it a point to give the postulates an
explicit place in his methodology. Furthermore, he notes that
postulates cannot just be accepted willy-nilly, but one must still
justify why such a postulate has been presumed,
The
core of a learned discussion is still formed by statements that are
taken as completely true. Some of these derive their justification
from proofs, and these can then be divided into axioms, propositions
etc. Here Hoffmann does not differ much from Wolff, although Hoffmann
doesn't define axioms as self-evident principle, but as principles
taken as granted in some discipline, although perhaps proven by
another, higher discipline.
More
interesting is Hoffmann's division of statements based on sensation
(Empfindung), the second type of statements taken as
completely true. Such statements include, quite expectedly,
statements based on experience, which Hoffmann calls also immediate
existential statements. Immediate existential statements might then
be based on common experience, in which we immediately sense some
objects and their connection : for instance, we might see in an
experience that air can be compressed. On the other hand, the
immediate existential statements might also be based on reflective
experience, in which the objects are abstractions, but the connection
is still something sensed or experienced, for instance, when we note
that some avaricious persons are ambitious. In other words,
reflective experience appears to be behind more generalised
statements based on experience.
Interestingly,
Hoffmann thinks that statements based on sensation include also what
he calls immediate essential statements and which by their definition
seem to be Kantian analytical judgements – for instance, ”expanded
substance takes up more space than it used to” is immediately
essential, because the predicate just explains what the subject says.
The most radical suggestion here is that such analytical connections
between concepts should be based on sensations. The idea appears to
be that one can through an inner sensation view one's representations
and instantly see that some of them are essentially connected to one
another.
After
introducing all the types of statements one will meet in a learned
discussion, Hoffmann continues by defining the very notion of
philosophy, just like Wolffians, but once again, Hoffmann's
definition has some clear differences from Wolff's definition. What
they both do have in common is the assumption that philosophy is a
natural cognition, that is, different from the supernaturally
justified theology. Hoffmann also agrees with Wolff that philosophy
is not mere history or recounting – philosophy discovers truths
that are not obvious on plain sight. At the same time he is willing
to go further and discard even all mere descriptions of experiments
from philosophy – in Wolffian tractates these were often included
in the so-called experimental philosophy.
What
are then the hidden truths Hoffmann wants philosophy to study?
Firstly, they describe essence or nature of some things, since
essences are usually not something that we could just plainly see.
Furthermore, philosophy should also concern actually existing things,
since some of them, say God and other souls, we never can sense.
Indeed, Hoffmann goes even so far as to say that philosophy can never
be about mere possibilities, which is a direct denial of Wolff's
definition of philosophy as the science of possibilities.
There
is still one element missing from Hoffmann's definition of
philosophy, namely, restricting philosophy to eternal or unchanging
truths – or at least to truths which cannot naturally stop being
truths. One important group of topics removed from the field of
philosophy is then everything that is based on free choice of human
beings, such as specific arts giving techniques for actualising
certain purposes. Even such arts are still based on philosophy,
Hoffmann says, because the ultimate ends of all human actions are
stable, that is, based either on essence of humanity or on God's
immutable will.
As
we have now seen various disciplines which are not philosophy, we
should see what belongs to philosophy. Surprising is the inclusion of
medicine in philosophy, but indeed, facts about human health might
well be hidden and unchanging. Even mathematics is part of
philosophy, since mathematical truths are not dependent on human
choices. Still, Hoffmann wants to separate mathematics as a science
of extensa, like space, from philosophy proper, which should instead
study qualities.
The
difference between mathematics and philosophy proper is not that
first one deals with quantitative issues, since qualities might also
be quantified, Hoffman says. Instead, just like Kant would later do,
Hoffmann places the difference to the methodologies the two
disciplines use – clear battle cry against Wolff's wish to apply
mathematics to philosophy straightaway. Mathematical objects are such
that we can abstract them easily from all their surroundings, while
in case of qualities such abstraction is usually difficult, since
qualities interact with other things much easier. Thus, in
mathematics we may well take just an individual example of e.g.
triangle and define through this example all triangles. In case of
qualities, on the other hand, individual cases are so multifarious
that it is almost impossible to make such generalisations. Indeed,
while in case of mathematical objects one might easily use the
Wolffian standard of generative definition to characterise e.g.
circles, in case of qualities the genesis might affect the object to
be defined. Then again, simplicity of mathematical objects often
makes it futile to divided them into further types of objects, but
qualities can be divided just because of their multiple
characteristics and dealings with other students. All in all,
Hoffmann argues that philosophy proper must often satisfy itself with
mere probabilites, while mathematics must always use proper
deductions.
If
then move to Hoffman's division of philosophy proper, the basic
classification depends on whether one wants to study things that are
common to all possible worlds or things proper particularly to the
actual world. The first class consists of things, Hoffman says, like
God, space, time and spirits, which are then investigated by
metaphysics, while things of second class, like gold and lions, are
investigated by the so-called disciplinal philosophy. It is
interesting that Hoffmann is able to characterise metaphysics, while
in Wolffian tradition it was defined merely as a sum of certain
philosophical disciplines.
Indeed,
Hoffman's vision of metaphysics differs also substantially from
Wolffian, since one of the central parts of metaphysics in Wolff's
philosophy or cosmology is the major part of discplinal philosophy
with Hoffmann. Furthermore, cosmology of Hoffmann differs from
Wolffian cosmology, since Hoffmann's world is meant to explicitly
contain both human souls and material objects in it. In addition to
cosmology, disciplinal philosophy should contain study of nature,
study of human understanding and study of human will. Of these, the
study of human will is most developed by Hoffmann and is divided into
a discipline called thelematology, which supposedly studies things
dependent on nothing, but human will, such as laughter, and into
moral philosophy, which should study things dependent on both human
will and God. Moral philosophy Hoffmann then divided into prudence or
study of means and various disciplines studying different moral
principles, namely, natural theology, law of nature and ethics.
What
really interests Hoffmann here is, of course, logic, or as he prefers
to call it, the study of reason. Just like Wolff, Hoffmann appears to
prefer beginning study of philosophy from logic. General need for
logic arises from the need to know how to distinguish truth from
falsehoods. Hoffmann doesn't apparently say that this would belong
wholy to the province of logic, and in fact, distinguishes four
different ways we come to regard something as true, only one of which
he explicitly connects with logic. Firstly, we have immediate
sensations of things, such as seeing that some tower is tall.
Secondly, we sometimes notice that contradictory of something is
impossible to think and conclude that this something must then be
true. Both of these two methods Hoffmann takes to be fairly reliable.
The
two other methods for ascertaining truth of something are then not so
reliable. First of these resembles the second reliable method, but
whereas in that case thinking the contradictory was impossible, in
this case it should be just not something we can think easily or
vividly enough. In such a case Hoffmann says we believe something,
but cannot be as convinced of it as in the reliable case.
The
second unreliable method then depends on truths cohering with one
another in such a manner that knowing one truth can lead us to
recognise the truth of another thing. It is this coherence of truths
that is the peculiar topic of logic. In other words, Hoffmann
explains, there must be some reason why human understanding can move
from one truth to another. We may have some natural proneness for
discovering these reasons, which then forms what is called natural
logic. Just like Wolff, Hoffmann thinks it is the task of scientific
or artificial logic to generalise and clarify these reasons into
rules we could then use explicitly for recognising truths.
In
a Wolffian fashion, Hoffmann then divides logic into a theoretical
and pratical part, but in a novel fashion. Theoretical part, Hoffmann
says, should discover the reasons why our understanding is able to
know truths. First demand for this is to know the various capacities
understanding has and then to move on to the effects of the use of
these capacities – for these effects Hoffmann lends a Lockean term
”idea”, which appears roughly to correspond to what is called
usually in tradition of German philosophy representation or
Vorstellung. Ideas are then classified according to their
various characteristics, and their various relations, such as
subordination, opposition and general coherence, are considered.
Notions of clarity and distinctness of ideas are also taken into
account. The next topic consists then of combinations of ideas or
concepts, propositions and proofs.
All
of this sounds at least superficially Wolffian, but truly original is
Hoffmann's inclusion of an account of truth to the theoretical part
of logic, while wolffians had placed it into the practical side.
Hoffmann's justification of this choice is quite believable –
surely truth itself must also be a presupposition for knowing truths.
Practical
part of logic attempts then to give rules, by which to improve the
effects of understanding through various abstract rules.
Understandably, the division of practical logic follows quite closely
the division of theoretical logic. In addition, practical logic
should at least contain chapters on e.g. disputation.
The
preliminary outline of logic has then been set up. Next time, I'll
begin with Hoffman's account of the various capacities of
understanding.
Ei kommentteja:
Lähetä kommentti