As you might notice
from the question mark, I am not completely certain about the
publication year of the second part of Gottsched's Erste Gründe
der gesammten Weltweisheit. All
the external sources I've studied indicate only a publication year
for the first book, and because I've seen only later editions of the
book, I haven't had the chance to verify this from the original
source. Luckily, in the later editions Gottsched added
as a preface his own life story, in which he clearly tells that he
finished the second part in 1734. Whether the book was also published
in the same year I do not know, but it at least seems likely.
In
the same preface Gottsched also notes that his philosophical
textbooks had been accused of being mere copies of Thümmig's Latin
textbooks. Gottsched of course denies the accusation, but one must
admit that some influences especially in the ordering of different
topics appears indubitable. For instance, in the case of this second
part, concentrating on practical philosophy, Gottsched does not
follow Wolff's double division of practical philosophy into ethics
and politics, but divides first the whole practical philosophy in the
same manner as Thümmig, according to levels of generality: the books
begins with general account of practical philosophy, moves to natural
law and only at the next level introduces the distinction to ethics
and politics.
One
particular point I forgot to mention when discussing the first part
of the book was Gottsched'd definition of philosophy, which differs
interestingly from Wolffian definition: for Gottsched, philosophy is
a science for obtaining happiness. It is clear then that Gottsched
holds practical philosophy to be of primary importance in comparison
with theoretical philosophy, which merely serves as a presupposition
of practical philosophy – one must know e.g. ontological truths
about good and bad and pneumatological truths about human behaviour
to get anywhere in practical philosophy.
An
important assumption in practical philosophy is that human beings are
in some sense free, because practical philosophy is for Gottsched all
about free actions – you cannot make evaluations out of reflexes.
Freedom, on the other hand, is dependent on us understanding the
situation and choosing what to do in that situation – a person with
seriously weak understanding, such as a child, cannot then be deemed
free and therefore cannot be blamed for his actions.
Gottsched's
practical philosophy is thus rather intellectual. Even conscience is
for him, just like for Wolff, a faculty for making judgements and
involves always syllogistic reasoning: a person has a principle of
action (in such and such a situation do this), analyses the situation
(this is such an such a situation) and then just follows the
conclusion of the deduction. Gottsched also suggests that we could
use a sort of reverse reasoning out of their actions in certain
situations what their moral principles must be. He notices the
possibility of someone faking his behaviour, but has an amusing
solution: just make him drunk enough and he will soon reveal his true
colours.
Gottsched's
rules for evaluating the actions are consequentialist: a principle of
action cannot be good, if it won't lead to good consequences. He goes
even so far as to suggest that because all actions will ultimately
lead to either good or bad results, all actions are either good or
bad. It remains rather unclear how long the causal chain starting
from an action should be followed to determine its worth – if taken
to its utmost extreme of following the consequences to final end of
the world, it appears humanly impossible to say anything about the
goodness and badness of actions.
Then
again, worth of a human being cannot be seen in one action, but more
in the general disposition appearing in a number of actions.
Furthermore, even the most virtuous person might occasionally have
relapses to vicious behaviour because of human weaknesses. Highest
good for human beings is then more like a constant attempt to improve
one's behaviour and make it more and more virtuous – this is an
idea that will reoccur e.g. in writing's of Fichte.
In
a very Wolffian fashion Gottsched suggests that the ultimate
principle of action should be the demand to make everyone perfect,
oneself and others. The care for oneself leads obviously to one's
happiness, but it is more difficult to say in Wolffian case how the
care for others can be deduced from the assumption of one's own
perfection as an end. Gottsched avoids the paradox by noting that God
has bound all human beings into a republic ruled by God, which makes
it our business to care for citizens of all the universe.
Furthermore, Gottsched also points out the Wolffian answer that even
intuiting perfection makes one happy, thus making helping one's
fellow beings a reasonably prudent choice.
It
is this striving towards universal perfection that summarises the
content of the law of nature in Gottsched. This law of nature is in a
sense backed up by God, in the sense that he has decreed all the
causal laws leading from certain actions to certain consequences –
vicious action is such that leads to unhappy life, and the connection
of the two was the creation of God. Then again, all these causal
regularities exist within the world and can be read out of it through
a correct use of reason – in other words, we do not need any
supernatural revelation to know what is good and what is bad, and
even atheists could be convinced of the law of nature.
Gottdched
goes then on to further specific features of the law of nature, which
is divided, firstly, into duties belonging to all human beings, no
matter what their status (and these are classified familiarly into
duties towards God, oneself and other human beings), and secondly, to
duties pertaining to certain social roles in e.g. a household or a
commonwealth. While the law of nature with all its subduties contains
then the general principles for all actions, concrete guidance to
correct action is provided by the science of ethics and politics.
These fields of philosophical investigation tell us how to motivate
people to follow the duties implied in the law of nature.
Furthermore, they try to give suggestions how following the law of
nature becomes easier – one should e.g. educate oneself and tame
one's affects and similarly states should provide for both
intellectual and moral upbringing of its citizens. The shape of this
system has rather Wolffian air, but in small details there are
certain differences – for instance, Gottsched seems more willing
than Wolff to allow for people helping one another, e.g. with alms.
***
This is also a good
place to consider Gottsched as a philosopher in general, since I've
now read most of his important writings. He did write a book on
rhetoric and he also published a lot of of new editions on his
earlier books – especially in his book on poetry he modified the
text and added further material as times went by. And undoubtedly a
complete picture of Gottsched would have to take into account his
poetic achievement. Still, these three books are quite enough to see
what is essential particularly in his philosophy.
One can firstly
appreciate the role of Gottsched in popularising and summarising
central tenets of Wolffian philosophy, as he quite astoundingly
manages to make out of five long books (logic, metaphysics, physics,
ethics and politics) two books, which still feel complete and full
works. One must also appreciate Gottsched's willingness to not follow
Leibniz or Wolff slavishly: he adds new material from other writers
especially in the matter of natural sciences and even distances
himself from some key Leibnizian tenets, like pre-established
harmony. Still, one feels that none of this makes Gottsched a very
original thinker, but a mere compiler.
The most influential
part of Gottsched's ouvre is undoubtedly his poetic, but even here
one feels that it is more due to historical reasons of Gottsched just
doing in German-speaking world what no one had done before. The book
does have an original flair, even if much of the topics have been
borrowed from Aristotle, Horace and modern French writers. The same
moralising and rule preaching attitude that can be glimpsed in
Gottsched's work on practical philosophy shows its full sway in his
adherence to rigid rules and in his condemnation of whole genres of
poetry. No wonder then that the rising new generation of writers
didn't follow Gottsched's instructions.
But this is getting
too much ahead of the progress of times. While we now said adieu to
Gottsched, next time we will meet a rising star in German school
philosophy.
Ei kommentteja:
Lähetä kommentti