Just like the the investigation of
judgements, the investigation of syllogisms is much more extensive in
Wolff's Latin than in his German logic. While German logic
concentrated on the so-called first figure of syllogisms and noted
that all other figures could be reduced to the first figure, in Latin
logic Wolff goes through even the second and third figures of
syllogism. As I have adequately dealt with all these figures, I shall
not touch this topic anymore.
This still doesn't mean that I could
leave the rest of this text blank. The three figures all have
categorical judgements as premisses, thus, syllogisms of these
figures could be called categorical. As categorical judgements are
the simplest type of judgements, Wolff also calls them simple
syllogisms. In addition, we might also have syllogisms with
non-categorical premisses, which appropriately are then called
complex syllogisms. Wolff goes on to note that complex syllogisms
include at least hypothetical syllogisms, with one hypothetical
judgement as a premiss, and disjunctive syllogisms, with one
disjunctive judgement as a premiss. There is no indication that these
two are all the types of complex syllogisms, although Kant will later
appear to assume this.
Just like with the three figures, Wolff
is eager to show that we can simplify the variety of syllogisms. Now,
I failed to mention last time that Wolff appears not to take
disjunctive judgements in the form of the current propositional
logic, that is, as a combination of propositions (p or q). Instead,
he favours the notion of disjunctive judgements as a combination of
concepts: A is B or C. Furthermore, while in modern propositional
logic ”p or q” is meant to include the possibility that both p
and q are true, Wolffian ”A is B orC” is clearly meant to
indicate that A cannot be both B and C at the same time. Thus, a
disjunctive syllogism is then of the form
A is B or C
A is / is not B
Then A is not / is C
Wolff points out that we could then
understand the judgement ”A is B or C” as a combination of
hypothetical judgements ”if A is B, then it is not C” and ”if A
is not B, then it is C”. Clearly then disjunctive syllogisms can be
reduced to hypothetical judgements.
Wolff continues by noting that an
important part of hypothetical syllogisms, including all the
disjunctive syllogisms, could be reduced to categorical syllogisms,
namely, those in which both the antecedent and consequent of the
hypothetical judgement have the same subject, in other words, if the
syllogism is of the form:
If A is B, then A is C
A is B
Thus A is C
Wolff suggests that we could always
read such a syllogism in the following form:
All Bs are Cs
A is B
Thus, A is C
Problem is that in the original
syllogism the hypothetical might hold only for As. Consider the
following deduction:
If a triangle is a figure with two
equally large angles, then it is an equilateral triangle
This triangle is a figure with two equally
large angles
Thus, it is an equilateral triangle
Clearly the corresponding categorical
premiss ”all figures with two equally large angles are equilateral
triangles” is false. A possible solution is to restrict the scope of the middle term in the following manner:
All As that are Bs are Cs
This A is B
Thus, A is C
Still, even if the reduction works with
these hypothetical syllogisms, Wolff has to admit that it isn't so
easy in those cases, where the hypothetical judgement doesn't have a
subject shared by its antecedent and consequent.
Wolff also considers incomplete
syllogisms, which Aristotle had in his Rhetoric called enthymemes. In
practice, such entyhmemes are nothing but hidden syllogisms, where we
leave some premisses implicit. Thus, if I deduce ”I am hungry,
therefore I must eat” I am actually assuming the general premiss
”if someone is hungry, he must eat".
An important subdivision of enthymems
is formed by so-called immediate syllogisms, which according to the
tradition could be used to prove something without full syllogistic
trappings: an example includes ”All As are Bs, thus,
some As are Bs”. Wolff points out that we could add as a new
premiss the tautology ”some As are As” and then we would have a
normal categorical syllogism, albeit one with a tautology as a
premiss.
Somewhat more surprising is Wolff's
view that even inductions are enthymemes or deductions with implicit
assumptions. Namely, if we conclude from the fact that certain
individuals or species of things have a feature that this feature is
shared by whole of their common genus, we have assumed a further
premiss that what holds for an individual or a species holds also for
superior genera. It appears problematic to suppose that induction
could be deduction, but I would like to point out that it is not
meant to be valid deduction, because one of the premisses might well
be untrue – the inductive principle or possibility to generalise
might be wrong either absolutely or under some circumstances.
I might finally note that Wolff describes a possibility to concatenate syllogisms to form chains of
deduction or polysyllogisms and that the highest form of deduction or
demonstration can use only axioms, definitions, indubitable
experiences and previously proven propositions as premisses. Next time
we shall see what all this has to do with truth.
Ei kommentteja:
Lähetä kommentti