Whenever you see a philosophical text
talking about nothing, it's sure to be quite important. Although the
topic would seem rather void of any content, it is at least full of
all sorts of ambiguities. Kant himself noted that there are at least
four things that ”nothing” or Nichts
could mean, although understanding these meanings requires
understanding lot of Kantian philosophy. Here I am interested of a
bit simpler ambiguity.
Consider first
cases where we usually apply words like ”nothing”: ”there's
nothing here”, ”no one is coming” and so forth. All of these
examples indicate lack of some type entities – for instance, in the
second case, a lack of persons. ”Nothing” seems thus remnant of
what in modern set theory is known as empty set, a set with no
members. In case of ”nothing”, as used in ordinary language, this
lack is undoubtedly often just contextual: the first example can be
used in a room full of socks, if it is shoes we are looking for.
Now, just as
extension and intension in general have often been conflated, one
tends to find confusion between ”nothing” in the sense given
above (lack of entities) and concept having such ”nothing” as its
extension. Thus, one might find such sentences as ”gold mountain is
nothing”, when what is meant is that there are no golden
mountains. This is then the first ambiguity involved with
nothingness.
Wolff's notion of
nothing might at first sight appear to correspond with the first of
the senses indicated above – or at least Wolff notes that he uses
term ”nothing” as corresponding with the arithmetical notion of
nullity. Yet, the very definition of nothing Wolff gives points to
another direction. Nothing, says Wolff, is such that corresponds to
no notion – or as he later admits, it corresponds only to a
deceptive notion. Furthermore, Wolff explicates that it is the
principle of contradiction that explains when a notion is deceptive –
that is, contradiction makes a notion a deceptive and refers only to
nothing.
What we have here
is then yet another common notion of ”nothing”: lack of
possibility or impossibility. And just like with the very first
notion of ”nothing”, there is also the possibility to confuse
lack of possibility with a concept referring to such impossibility –
we can find sentences like ”round square is nothing”, when all
that is meant is that there cannot be any round squares. But what is
more interesting is the relation of ”nothing” as lack of
possibility to ”nothing” as lack of entities: we could describe
the former ”nothing” as a lack of possible entities and the
latter as a lack of actual entities. When Wolff then defines
”something” as a contradictory of ”nothing”, he must be
referring to a presence of possible entities – or to concepts
referring to such entities.
Now, one might
wonder, what has all this to do with the principle of sufficient
reason? Well, Wolff's infamous proof of the principle depends very
much on that ambiguous notion. Let us presume an existing thing A
without any reasons, Wolff begins. Then there is a ”nothingness”
of these reasons, but such nothingness cannot produce anything, which
contradicts the existence of A.
This rather curious
argument suffers clearly from the ambiguity of the notion of
”nothing”. What it appears to be trying to deduce at first sight
is that a lack of any reasons or grounds would fail to produce
anything. Yet, as we have seen, Wolffian notion of nothingness does
not refer to such lack of actual entities, but to a lack of possible
entities. The starting point of the indirect proof is then the
assumption that thing A couldn't have any reasons, that is, that its
generation would be inexplicable impossibility. This clearly would contradict the
very existence of A, which would indeed have to be possible, thus
leading to the sought for conclusion or the denial of this
nothingness.
Wolff's argument
can then be maintained, but then its conclusion comes out as rather
trivial. Wolff has shown that without any possibility of
generating something, this something could not be, or in other words,
that if something exists, there must be some possible way it has come
into existence. It is then not necessary that this possible
generation process would have been a deterministic causal link
necessitating it, but it merely should have been a possible series of
events leading to the existence of the particular thing. On the other
hand, this fits well with Wolff's wish to account for non-causal
chains of grounding in human action. Motives need not determine our
actions, but they just need to open up a possible path for them –
it might still be down to our choice, which path is taken.
What is more
difficult to reconcile with this weak reading of the principle of
sufficient reason is Wolff's second argument for the principle.
Supposedly one could distinguish reality from dreams only through the
principle of sufficient reason: while the former follows the
principle, in the latter there happen all sorts of changes just
willy-nilly or according to the whimsy of the dreamer. If the
principle would be taken in the weaker sense, then there would be no
contradiction between it and dreams, because even the most absurd
dream sequences still are possible sequences.
Now, although the
dream argument appears to speak for a stronger sense of the
principle, it is not impossible to make it agree with the weaker
sense also. Wolff might not be thinking of dreams contradicting the
principle itself, but a conjunction of the principle with relevant
physical laws. Thus, while e.g. sequence of me flying above the
clouds would not be impossible as such, it would be impossible given
the physical laws preventing such flight. This reading would actually
make more sense, because when Wolff does say that the principle of
sufficient reason is derivable from the principle of contradiction,
anything contradicting principle of sufficient reason would be
contradictory and impossible – which appears rather confusing, when
we evidently can experience dream sequences.
This conclusion
appears rather interesting, because early on it was the dream
argument that was emphasised by the followers of Wolff. It seems
plausible that this argument was chosen over the official proof of
Wolff himself, because it was easier to reconcile with the stronger
version of the principle of sufficient reason. In effect, the dream
argument then gives a criterion for recognising reality: it is the
lawlike nature of the reality that distinguishes it from dreams. One
might even find such emphasis on lawlikeness in Kant's description of
experience as regulated by the category of causality. If the weaker
reading of the principle is correct in case of Wolff, his description
of reality is far more modest: it is not the lawlikeness as such that
distinguishes reality from dreams, but the fact that reality follows
laws not followed by dreams.
So much for
sufficient reasons, next time I'll look at essences.
Ei kommentteja:
Lähetä kommentti