One important result
of the theoretical part of Hoffmann's logic was to understand the
importance of the clarity of our ideas, but also to note the
ambiguity of what clarity means – it is quite a different matter to
have sensational clarity than analytical clarity. Now, Hoffmann notes
that it is either quite easy to make our ideas sensationally clear –
if we have forgotten what an apple looks like, we just have to go out
and see an apple – or then it is quite impossible – we cannot
sense things like courage, for instance. The case of analytical
clarity is more intricate, and definitions, or combinations of
abstractions resulting from analysis, are the primary tool for
gaining it.
Hoffmann's
definition of definition starts from an actual explanation of how
definitions are formed – first, we analyse our ideas, then we
combine the analysed abstractions in order to see how our original
ideas consist of certain features or to find completely new ideas. He
declares that this is far more satisfying way to define definitions
than just describing them as revealing the essence of things – such
a definition does not yet tell how we can discover the structure of
any essence. Only slightly better is to characterise definition as a
combination of genus and differentia, which actually says merely that
all things share properties with other things, but also differ from
them. Its main fault lies in suggesting that all definitions must
have such a structure, although one might also define an idea as a
common element in several genera (just like humans can be defined as
belonging to both genus of animals and to genus of rational
entities).
Equally erroneous,
Hoffmann thinks, are the usual ways of differentiating between
nominal and real definitions. Nominal definitions cannot be mere
explanations of words compared to real definitions as explanations of
things, since in explaining how a word is used, one is also
explaining what sort of thing one is speaking of. Furthermore,
nominal definitions are not defined by consisting of mere sensuous
ideas, since we can well have nominal definitions of e.g. character
traits. Most importantly, Hoffmann denies the validity of equating
real definitions with generative definitions, since one and the same
thing might be generated in many ways, and one and the same method of
generation might produce many different kinds of things.
Instead, Hoffmann
thinks that the division between nominal and real definition lies in
difference between possibility and actuality. Nominal definitions are
such that define mere ideas, and all they need is general coherence.
Real definitions, on the other hand, should refer to things beyond
mere ideas, and thus, when announcing a real definition, one should
take care that the definition defines something that truly
exists.
Rest of Hoffmann's
tale of definitions concentrates then on real definitions. The most
important division of them consists of what Hoffmann calls first
concepts. The idea behind this notion is somewhat complex. Hoffmann
thinks that all real definitions should be justified through
something. One possibility is to justify them through other concepts
and their real definitions, but obviously this route cannot go on
indefinitely. Thus, at some point we must come to concepts,
definitions of which have to be justified through things themselves,
and these then are the first concepts.
Such concepts might
describe individual properties of things, but also combinations of
such properties or essences, which might be essences of either
naturally or artificially produced things and which might be either
necessary combinations (like three angles with three sides) or
contingent (like heaviness with gold). In general, first concepts
divide into five classes. There are relative essences, consisting of
mere ideal relations, mathematical essences, consisting of mere
quantitative properties, existential essences, consisting of
existentially connected properties, physical essences, consisting of
causes and effects, and moral essences, consisting of means and
purposes.
All these essences
have different ways to be defined, Hoffmann remarks. Relations can be
defined only through the properties of what is related, while
mathematical essences can be defined either through their method of
generation or through their sensuous properties. Definitions of
physical essences depend on whether the things in question are
natural or artificial: natural physical things might be defined by
their method of generation, their various sensuous properties and
causal powers and their relations to other things, while artificial
physical things are defined by their structure and their purpose.
While moral essences in general should be defined just in case of
purposes and means, especially in case of rights and obligations one
must also consider conditions in which those rights and obligations
can be actualized.
Finally, existential
essences can be defined through various means. Firstly, they can be
defined through sensuous changes affected by them – for instance,
substance is something that subsists by itself, that is, that we can
see to exist in various places, not bounded to another thing.
Secondly, they can be defined through their inexisting parts or
abstractions – for instance, a real thing can be defined through
its abstracted properties of a) being thinkable and b) existing
outside thinking. Finally, they can be defined by explaining their
method of abstraction – for instance, extension is that which is
left of a spatial thing, when we abstract from its forces and from the
substrate behind them.
Hoffmann also
considers whether one needs some further essences, notably in
metaphysics or logic. In case of metaphysics, Hoffmann can just note
that all essences handled in it, fall into some already dealt cases.
Same holds in logic, where e.g. a concept of subject is relational
and concept of deduction is causal.
First concepts serve
as a beginning of definition, and Hoffmann characterises all further
forms of real definition also through their purpose in cognition. He
also notices that some definitions might actually have various
purposes and thus fall into more than one kind. Furthermore, he
mentions fascinatingly that some definitions, what he calls ignoble,
serve no purpose at all – unfortunately, he provides no example of
such an intriguing class.
The two true classes
of real definition, which are not first concepts, are characteristic definitions, which help to distinguish things, and causal
definitions, which help to explain sensuous properties of a thing.
The two classes overlap one another, as Hoffmann already implied.
Starting from causal definitions, it is not so much the existence,
but properties of things that are explained by them – the
definition begins from the essence of a thing and thus can be used a
premiss to explain why the thing has this or that property. This is a
very wide understanding of causality and could be applied also e.g.
to mathematical things.
Characteristic
definition, then, might actually be also a causal definition – by
showing the essence of a thing, we also make it possible to
distinguish it from other things. This sort of characteristic
definition Hoffmann calls a priori, but he also accepts a posteriori
characteristic definitions, which are clearly non-causal – in these
definitions, we distinguish a thing through some conditions we find
it in.
This concludes
Hoffmann's theory of definitions. Next, he will handle divisions.
Ei kommentteja:
Lähetä kommentti