Next task in
Hoffmann's logic is to investigate the various relations ideas might
have to one another. Here the notion of grounding plays an important
role: in a pair of two ideas, either one is a ground of existence for
the other or then neither is, that is, either one cannot exist
without the other or both can exist independently. The former
possibility Hoffmann calls subordination, and it contains a subset
consisting of pairs in which both ideas could be the ground and were
thus necessary to one another's existence – in that case, the ideas
are said to be equal, somewhat like 12 – 3 and 9. Note that in the
case of subordination, one can always abstract from the grounding
idea the other idea. This does not mean that the possibility of
abstraction would be a sufficient criterion for recognising
subordination, since in case of external abstraction (for instance,
when we abstract time and place from a concrete event), what is
abstracted is not subordinated to the starting point of abstraction,
because e.g. certain time can exist without an event occurring in it.
As we saw in the
previous post, in many cases Hoffmann distinguishes between cases
where things truly have some structure and cases where the things
have this structure only in relation to understanding. In case of
subordination, we might speak of absolute and relative subordination,
where relative subordination means cases in which subordination
exists only in thought, because we have abstracted both sides of the
subordination at the same time. An example would be the notional pair
of high and low. We couldn't call anything high without at the same
time assuming the existence of some relatively low places and vice
versa, but places that we happen to call high might well exist
without the places we happen to call low – we just wouldn't call
them high in that case.
The notions of relative and absolute subordination are not clearly divided, since from cases of absolute or proper subordination we can produce examples of relations, if we move to a new order of abstraction. That is, birds and animals form one example of a proper subordination, since birds cannot exist without animals existing. Yet, we can abstract from the relation of birds and animals the more abstract relation of genus and species. The notions of genus and species are then relations, since both notions are dependent of the other – while animals could exist without bird existing, no genus can exist without some species.
The notions of relative and absolute subordination are not clearly divided, since from cases of absolute or proper subordination we can produce examples of relations, if we move to a new order of abstraction. That is, birds and animals form one example of a proper subordination, since birds cannot exist without animals existing. Yet, we can abstract from the relation of birds and animals the more abstract relation of genus and species. The notions of genus and species are then relations, since both notions are dependent of the other – while animals could exist without bird existing, no genus can exist without some species.
Although relations
are then, according to Hoffmann, somewhat dependent on understanding,
we can still distinguish between proper and accidental relations. In
latter it is not so much a case of relations that are not really
relations, but of relations that are not as natural as could be.
Thus, the idea of species is naturally related to the idea of the
closest genus, but only accidentally related to the idea of a more
proximate genus.
In an absolute
subordination, one type consists of cases where the subordinated
actually exists in its ground. This could either mean metaphysical
subordination, in which the ground is subject and subordinate is
something subsisting in that subject, like figures subsist in matter,
or existential subordination, in which the subordinated is a part of
the ground, which is then its respective whole. Hoffmann only
mentions the metaphysical subordination and concentrates mostly on
the existential subordination.
Existential
subordination is then just another name for the relation of whole and
part. Hoffmann notes that there are in fact many wholes. Whole could
be an essential whole and the subordination then essentially
qualitative, in which parts are independent of one another and also
of the whole: this is the relation between humans and their souls.
Then again, whole could be an integral whole and the subordination
then quantitative, in which parts cannot really be detached from one
another nor from the whole: this is a relationship holding between
numbers, like 6 and 12. Slightly different is the case in essential
mathematical subordination, in which a whole is essentially
mathematical and parts can at least in thought be separated from the
whole, since they are of completely different type, like sides of a
triangle as lines differ from the two-dimensional triangle. But most
interested Hoffmann is of the logical subordination, in which whole
is a logical whole, like animality, and its parts (different types of
animals) share the essence with the whole, but can be separated from
one another.
Logical
subordination is then either total – both ideas are subordinates of
the other, just like rational animal and animal capable of
deliberation – or then partial, in which only one of the ideas is
subordinated to the other. The partial logical subordination seems on
a closer look just another name for the relation of some genus to a
species – the genus is considered extensionally as a class of
individuals and species is then a part of this class. One could then
think that there isn't that much of interest that Hoffmann could
really say about this tired old topic. Yet, it is of interest how
Hoffmann notes that this relation has varieties differing from the
usual norm embodied in the classification of living creatures.
Thus, just like in
many other cases, logical abstraction might be accidentally logical,
or it might hide a further, non-logical abstraction within it –
thus, when I seemingly subordinate the species of electric eel to a
genus of animals capable of producing electricity, I am actually
describing its causal capacities. Even in properly logical
abstraction, the connection between supposed genus and idea might be
just accidental. For instance, when I divide learned persons into
those who are pious and those who are not, the piety is not
intrinsically connected with being learned. Indeed, one might as well
begin with a class of pious persons and divide them into learned and
unlearned
Then again, the
supposed genus might also be impure in the sense that it contains
attributes not necessarily existing in the species. Thus, Hoffmann
says, we might speak of the idea of a theologian and consider it as a
species in the genus of academics, yet the genus would be impure,
because a theologian need not be academically learned person. In
addition, genus might also be incomplete in the sense that what
belonging to a genus means might be dependent on what the more
determined species if. As an example Hoffmann notes the idea of
correspondence: the notion is incomplete, since correspondence
between, on the one hand, a picture and the original, and on the
other hand, purpose and means are quite different in nature.
Hoffmann's divisions
of different modes of logical subordination serve then once again to
reveal paralogisms in reasoning. Even more so is the case of
distinguishing cases where the subordination between ideas is based
more on possible connection, that is, where the ground, as it were,
potentially contains the subordinated idea. This is what happens in
various causal relations, in which then, Hoffmann thinks, cause and
effect must be necessarily connected.
When we are speaking
of causes, Hoffmann elucidates, we might be either discussing proper
or efficient causes or then mere ground of possibility, which merely
determines a simultaneously existing thing, which is then dependent
on the ground, but still not created by it, just like two sides and
an angle determine the rest of the constituents of a triangle.
Hoffmann complains that Leibnizians have often confused the two
topics, speaking of proper causes, when all they had was a ground of
possibility and sometimes even just an ideal ground for cognising
something. Cause is a ground, but its a very peculiar type of ground.
It is then of
interest for Hoffmann to distinctly separate proper causes from
various grounds. Thus, Hoffmann notes, cause must have existed
previous to the effect it causes – hence, if world is eternal we
cannot say that God has caused its existence. Furthermore, cause must
have proper force, by which it makes something happen – thus,
unlike Descartes thought, mere geometrical shapes cannot be causes of
anything. Finally, force must be directed to produce this very effect
– hence, in Leibnizian pre-established harmony soul cannot be said
to be cause of bodily movements, since the force of soul is directed
only to changes in soul itself.
An important notions
pertaining to causes and grounds are perfection and sufficiency.
Cause is perfect, Hoffmann defines, when the cause is the cause of
the whole effect, down to every last detail and circumstance. Ground
is sufficient, on the other hand, when it lack nothing that is
required to make what it is ground of to exist. Imperfect cause is
might still be sufficient – it just cannot account for all the
details of it has made to exist. Then again, a cause that is an
insufficient ground, is always sufficient ground for some detail in
what has been caused.
A perfect cause must
then account for why something exists, why it has the properties it
has and why it continues existing. All of these three aspects must be
based on some acting force in the cause. All of these causes might
then be analysed into various partial causes and grounds. For
instance, within a cause of existence one might distinguish between
sufficient cause of existence, which truly makes that something to
appear, and efficient cause of possibility, which merely adds some
ground to make the final result possible. For example, in case of
sensation, the human body acts like a cause of possibility –
without bodies we couldn't sense – but the actual sufficient cause
is the thing affecting sense organs.
Causes in general
can be analysed into various constituents, Hoffmann notes. Firstly,
there is the cause as a concrete subject with a certain active force
directed to something – this is what Hoffmann calls principal
cause. Then again, we might abstract from the fact that this force
belongs to some concrete subject – then we are investigating merely
the causality or act of causation. We might also be interested just
of the impulsive cause or the events that the cause makes happen and
activates. Finally, we might be interested of the various modes or
intermediaries between the act of principal cause and the final
impulsive cause.
The principal cause
might be mechanical or act merely through figure and magnitude of
matter, like force and pressure of lever. Then again, it might also
be physical or based on inner activities of matter, like movements of
elements. It might also be ideal or based on understanding and ideas,
like memory can be caused by sensations. Finally, it might be
voluntary or based on force of will acting toward some end, like
reproductive urges of animals.
Of the various types
of principal causes, Hoffmann is especially interested of voluntary
causes. Voluntary causes, he says, can be physical or unintentional,
like a feeling of desperation, or they might be intentional or moral,
like love. Focusing on moral causes, Hoffmann notes that these can be
analysed into the act of will in pursuing something or the subjective
final cause, the object that the subjective final cause strives to
make happen or objective final cause and the intermediary effects of
subjective final cause meant to produce the objective final cause or
means. All the three notions can then be further analysed and
classified: for instance, we can regard the means merely as the
formal activity directed toward some end or as a material object,
like gold, good for making some things happen.
Moving then from
principal to impulsive causes or from the subject of causation to the
events caused, Hoffmann notes that these either mechanically make
some other forces act, like compressing air makes it expand later, or
then ideally affects some spiritual entity, like some sensations make
a person anxious. Hoffmann is again more interested of the affairs of
persons and notes that ideal impulsive causes are either natural,
that is, not caused by a free agent, like certain bodily reactions
may make us feel uncomfortable, or moral, that is, caused by a free
agent, like a piece of oratory may arouse in us some emotions.
Hoffmann also notes that some ideal impulsive causes may be internal
to the person affected, somewhat like anger might make us act
aggressively. These internal impulsive causes must then be carefully
distinguished from final causes, since the former are not
intentional.
Finally, Hoffmann
speaks of the intermediary modes. Of course, an act of causation
might not use any intermediaries, but if it does, these either
somehow modify the events caused or then merely remove some obstacles
preventing them. They may mere passive instruments of the principal
cause or they may have their own active force meddling with the
proceedings, and they might be either necessary requirements or not.
An important subgroup is formed by what Hoffmann calls objective
causes, that is, the nature of the object of causation itself
modifying the act of causation.
Hoffmann also notes
that causation might activate only relativistic effects, that is,
effects occurring only within an understanding. Thus, when summer
changes into winter, nothing happens with a temperature of well
insulated cellar, but to human touch the cellar now feels warmer.
Completely different matter are then accidental causes, for instance,
when a known gambler happens to lose all his fortune playing cards
and because of that changes his complete lifestyle. In such an
accidental causation, the cause itself is not directed toward the
effect that follows it or it is not controlling cause, unlike in a
case, where a gambler changes his lifestyle because of a convincing
speech made by his psychiatrist. This does not mean that such a
controlling cause could be certain – psychiatrists cannot help all
their patients – but might be assisted or prevented by various
external factors. Indeed, Hoffmann goes on to classify various grades
of certainty in causal acts: causation might be e.g. such that it
cannot be stopped, once it has started to affect, or then it might be
prevented, although its effects are otherwise quite certain, like
death caused by cutting of the artery might still be prevented by
quick surgery.
Hoffmann's account
of subordination is thus full of detailed analysis and classification
of various relations, and especially his study of causality is quite
extensive for a book that is supposed to concern only logic. Next
time I'll take a look of what more Hoffmann has still to say about
relations between ideas and deal especially with varieties of
opposition.
Ei kommentteja:
Lähetä kommentti