I have often wondered where Kant got
the idea of dividing judgments into analytic and synthetic, analytic
referring to judgments where the content of the predicate was
included in the content of the subject and synthetic referring then
obviously to judgements where this inclusion did not hold. It's not
any difficulty in the definitions I am speaking of, but of the
nomenclature that would have in Kant's days reminded the reader of
two different methods of reasoning, analysis and synthesis.
Originally analysis and synthesis were
used by Greek geometers as referring to processes that mirrored one
another. In analysis, one assumed that the required conclusion –
proposition to be proved or a figure to be constructed – was
already known or in existence. One then had to go through the
conditions of this conclusion in order to find self-evident
principles on which the conclusion could be based.
If analysis moved from conclusions to
premisses, the synthesis moved the other way. One began from some
principles already assumed or demonstrated to be true and from
methods that one already knew how to use, and from these principles
and methods set out to prove some new theorem or to draw a new sort
of figure.
A certain step in the evolution of the
mathematical methods into Kantian judgement types is symbolised by
Rüdiger's notion of analysis and synthesis. Just like in the
tradition, Rüdiger uses analysis for a method moving from
consequences to principles behind them. Yet, he also calls such
method judicial and separates it from synthetic method, which he describes as invention.
That is, analysis does not produce any new information, just like in
Kant's analytic judgement predicate does not reveal anything that
wouldn't already be in the subject. Instead, analysis merely
determines whether a given proposition is clearly true or at least
probable.
Rüdiger's account of synthesis or
invention of new and informative truths includes even more
aberrations from the traditional account. For Rüdiger, synthesis
might involve also mere probable conclusions that are based on the
correspondence of various sensations – for instance, by seeing that
a certain effect follows always from certain conditions, we may
conclude that a new occurence of similar conditions would probably
lead to similar effects. Here we see Rüdiger's empiricist leanings,
but he does not restrict synthesis to mere empirical generalisations
– in addition he also accepts necessary demonstrations.
Rüdiger divides demonstrations into
three classes, according to three components required for thinking.
One type is based on the verbal form of thinking and grammar: for
instance, we deduce from the statement that Jane hit Mary the related
statement that Mary was hit by Jane. The second type contains various
forms of reasoning, such as traditional syllogisms, but the common
element Rüdiger suggests is that all of them are based on the
relations of ideas – we might name these forms logical.
By far the most interesting is the
third type of reasoning, the mathematical. Leibniz and Wolff had
thought that mathematics was based on inevitable axioms and even
empiricists like Hume grouped mathematics with logical reasoning.
Rüdiger, on the other hand, clearly separates logic and mathematics.
Logical reasoning is based on the relations of ideas, while
mathematics is based on the sensuous element of thinking.
Rüdiger's position shares some
interesting similarities with Kant's ideas on mathematics. Both Kant
and Rüdiger are convinced that mathematics are not mere logic, but
synthetic or inventive. True, Kant speaks of mathematics as based on
intuitions, while Rüdiger speaks of sensations, but this might not
be as great a difference as it first seems. Rüdigerian concept of
sensation is clearly more extensive than Kant's and would probably
include also what Kant called pure intuitions. Indeed, Rüdiger also
separates mathematical reasoning from mere empirical generalisations
– mathematical truths are not mere probabilities.
The reason behind Rüdiger's desire to
separate mathematics from logic is also of interest. Once again
Spinoza is the devil that one wants to excommunicate. Spinoza's
Ethics is supposedly philosophy in a mathematical form, but Rüdiger
notes that this is intrinsically impossible. Mathematics can rely on
certain sensations, when it constructs its definitions and divisions
– it can tell that triangle is a meaningful concept, because it
can draw triangles. Philosophy, on other hand, does not have a similar
possibility for infallibly finding sensations for its concepts – a very Kantian
thought.
So much for Rüdiger this time. Next
time we are back with Wolffian philosophy.
An instructive analysis (pardon the pun) of these quite complicated problems can be found in H.-J. Engfer, Philosophie als Analysis, Stuttgart-Bad Canstatt 1982.
VastaaPoistaThank you for the recommendation, I'll have to look at at it!
VastaaPoista