When one for the first time hears
Leibnizian principle of sufficient reason, it seems quite obvious and
self-evident: of course, everything happens for a reason. But as
Samuel Clarke was quick to notice, the innocent appearing principle
could be used for smuggling substantial presuppositions behind our backs. For
instance, Leibniz himself used the principle to justify the more
uncertain principle of the identity of indiscernibles: God could not have created two exactly similar things, because God would have no ground for choosing the situations of the two things.
Wolff begins the chapter on natural
theology by a similar abuse of the principle of sufficient reason.
Theology itself is probably a familiar term to everyone, but what
makes it natural? The answer is that natural theology is supposedly
based on mere human reason, while the other type of theology – that
is, revealed – is based on supposed divine revelation.
Wolff thus supposes that a sufficient
reason is only such that requires no reason beyond itself. In effect,
Wolff has not been demanding just an explanation, but a full
explanation of everything, ending with a final term that is
self-explanatory. And as we might remember from previous texts,
Wolffian ground/reason is not just any explanation, but a causal
agent actualising things. The principle of the sufficient reason is
hence suddenly turned into a commitment for the existence of a final
instigator of causal things. That is, to a commitment that while
normal possible things require some external force to overcome the
opposite possibility of their non-existence, there is a thing that
has enough force in itself for self-actualisation.
It takes no theologian to guess that
this self-actualising thing, which cannot fail to exist, is meant to
be the traditional God: a transcendent being beyond both the physical
world and the realm of human souls. One might still wonder why Wolff
accepts only a single self-actualising thing. After all, the causal
chains in the world might have more than one beginning, that is,
there might well be more than one God.
Although Wolff does not directly answer
this problem, he does try to argue against the identification of
humans and God on the basis of the possible multiplicity of human
souls. Wolff notes that when one accepts the existence of the world,
it is easy to see that the human soul as dependent on the world
cannot be God. Idealists, who deny the existence of the world,
and even what Wolff calls egoists and what we would call solipsists, that is, philosophers admitting only their own existence, admit at least that there are many possible human souls. Yet, just
this plurality of souls makes it impossible that the humans would be
Gods. Plurality of possible Gods is apparently against the necessity
of the supposed God: if a thing might be otherwise and still a God,
it would require a further ground why the thing then is like it
actually is, thus, it surely couldn't be self-actualising and
self-explaining.
When it comes to God's characteristics,
Wolff follows tradition: God is, for instance, capable of intuiting
all things immediately, thus, requires no symbolic knowledge; he is
wise, that is, capable of planning the relationships between the
things in the most perfect manner possible; he also lives in the
highest possible bliss, because he sees the perfection of the world.
But what interests us most is the relationship between the God and
the world.
Until now, the status of the
possibilities or essences in Wolffian philosophy has been rather
unclear: on the one hand, essences are said to be eternal and thus existing, on the
other hand, they are not actualised. Wolff suggests that it is the
understanding of God that sustains all the various possibilities:
they exist in a sense, because God is continuously thinking all of
them.
Although God thinks all the
possibilities and especially all possible worlds, this does not still
make them actual. Instead, actuality is received through a force,
which is external, if the actualised thing is not God, and
ultimately, through God’s will.
Interestingly, this characterisation is
connected to Wolff’s notion of philosophy as a science of
possibilities. Although the understanding of humans is not as pure as
God’s – that is, it is confused or sensous – we can at least
partially follow what is going on in God’s understanding, because
the content of his understanding is necessary: that is, there can be
no other possibilities. Then again, what is actual depends on God’s
choice and the motives behind it. Thus, we can know generally that
God has chosen the best possible world, but we cannot with certainty
say that a particular chain of events would belong to the best
possible world – in other words, there cannot be any true science
of actualities.
*******************************************************************************
Because I have finally reached the end
of Wolff’s German Magnum Opus, this is a great opportunity to
evaluate the whole book. The historical worth of Wolff’s German
metaphysics is unquestionable. Although there had been philosophical
books written in German, Wolff’s book was still the most systematic
treatment of all the major topics of traditional metaphysics, and as
we shall most likely see in the distant future, its influence can
still be felt in Kant’s writings. That said, we might still
question the originality of his work in a wider perspective of the
Europian philosophy in 18th century: I shall say a little bit
about this topic in the next post.
Does German metaphysics then hold any
interest for a modern philosopher? As we have witnessed, the book is
full of gaps in argumentation, unwarranted presuppositions and plain
sophisms. Still, one must appreciate at least the architectural
design of the book, where in the ontology the classification into
three main types of things – complex or material things and
especially the world, simle, but finite things and especially souls,
and the infinite thing or God – is introduced and where the final
chapter ties all the knots by showing how both the material world and
the souls are dependent on the God.
Wolff's German metaphysics has finally
ended. I have been rather longwinded on the topic, but I have felt
this has been necessary, because of the historical importance of the
book. Next time, I shall make a short detour on an earlier
philosopher: we shall meet the supposed predecessor of Wolff.
Ei kommentteja:
Lähetä kommentti